(Warning: a rambling disquisition about the point of just war theory in history. Tries to articulate some thoughts I've been nursing for the last couple of months, and some things I've tried to say in my class on political philosophy and international relations).
How should one respond to the fact of war? I do not mean how
we ought to respond to this or that war, but about the enduring fact that human
beings engage in warfare: what should we
do about this fact, at the most general level, if anything? And in particular, what constitutes a proper philosophical response to the fact of war?
One common response to the fact of warfare is articulated by
the theory of just war. Just war theory presupposes that war is an unfortunate
but sometimes unavoidable aspect of the human condition: given some general facts
about human psychology (for example, the fact that at least some people lust for power or strongly
believe that particular ideologies must be imposed on others), we must expect
war to flare up from time to time, though its frequency may wax and wane for a
variety of reasons (demographic, technological, cultural, etc.). Yet some of
these wars will be justifiable: there
will be good reason for (some people) to fight them in order to protect
important values. The proper response to the fact of warfare thus involves
articulating the principles and rules that distinguish between justifiable and
unjustifiable wars (and between justifiable and unjustifiable conduct in war),
and appealing to or forcing those who engage in that practice to regulate their
conduct according to these principles and rules; and at least the first task necessarily
involves philosophical reflection.
The ideal here is not the elimination of war, but the
reduction of unjustifiable war through the moral (and sometimes legal)
regulation of the practice. And though this regulation may take institutional form (as it does, imperfectly, nowadays), it
need not: all the just war theorist presumes is that most people are relatively
receptive to moral argument, at least when such moral argument appeals to
relatively noncontroversial principles and is presented in a clear way. And even
if such appeals sometimes fall on deaf ears, the just war theorist assumes that
they are not entirely ineffectual. One
can appeal to the conscience of those in power, even if sometimes they have
trouble hearing its voice, or at least force them to pay a decent respect to
the opinions of others, and one can train those who actually fight to be
responsive to moral precepts that constrain what they can do in the heat of
battle.
The basic principles of just war theory seem to have a
certain universal appeal, given that they have changed little since Aquinas articulated them
in the 13th century. (And he was merely systematizing ideas that
were even older, going back to Cicero and the Stoics in the late Roman
Republic). We still discuss ius ad bellum
in terms of the basic triad of proper authority (who can authorize a war?),
just cause (is there a good reason to fight, and in particular a reason that
can justify the collective use of armed force?), and right intention (is the
just cause merely a pretext for more nefarious purposes, or do the people waging
war genuinely intend to protect some important values by going to war?). Other
principles – like “reasonable chance of success” – sometimes enter the
discussion, but the basic framework remains ancient. Witness the debate about
the recent intervention in Libya, for example. Disagreement about the morality
of the intervention revolved around the questions of who had the authority, if
anyone, to permit the use of armed force against Gaddafi’s government, whether
Gaddafi’s actions to put down a rebellion against his government gave other
countries a good reason for engaging in war against him, and whether NATO
members genuinely intended to protect Libyan civilians and/or help the Libyan
rebels overthrow an oppressive regime (or were, on the contrary, acting to
secure control over Libya’s oil or Western influence in the Middle East). Similarly,
debates about the morality of particular tactics in bello (e.g., the use of precision munitions to attack particular
people in urban areas) all revolve around the basic triad of principles of innocent
immunity (is the target a civilian or a combatant?), proportionality (are the
means proportionate to the end, or are they “overkill”?), and double effect
(are the deaths of civilians a genuinely unavoidable result of the use of
proportionate means?). Though the full articulation of the principles of ius in bello is of somewhat more recent
vintage (they are more
sketchily described in Aquinas than the principles of ius ad bellum, for example), they are still quite old and broadly
accepted.
But though the basic principles of just war theory are widely
accepted, the fact of disagreement obviously indicates that their application is much more controversial.
The more one moves from broad principles to specific rules and even more to
particular judgments the less arguments about the justice of particular wars or
tactics will be convincing. Arguments come to depend on distinctions that are
far less obvious and much more contestable. For example, the US Air Force consistently
argues (and I’m sure mostly in good faith; as far as I know, American soldiers do
receive explicit training on the principles of just conduct in war) that its use
of precision munitions respects all the basic principles of ius in bello: such munitions are used
only against people which intelligence indicates are “combatants” and responsible
people attempt to minimize “collateral damage” (i.e., apply the proportionality
and double effect principles). Yet many people vocally disagree with them about
all aspects of this argument, including the weight that should be given to the evidence
of combatant status (what is the acceptable false positive rate for a target?)
and whether the use of 500 pound weapons in urban areas represents due care for
the lives of non-combatants (what is the acceptable rate of civilian death from
attacks on genuine military targets?).
The problem is not that
there is no right answer to these questions, but that no particular answer can depend on premises that are all widely acceptable. Many if not most positions can
muster plausible arguments (I get a glimpse of this every year when I ask my
students to write essays applying the principles of just war to various recent
military conflicts). Even sincere attempts by serious and well-trained thinkers
to apply these principles to particular conflicts lead to ambiguous results. When
one reads Vitoria’s
exhaustive examination (in the 16th century) of what would count
as a just cause of war against the natives of the Americas (and hence would
justify conquering them and taking their land), it is hard to say for sure
whether he supported or opposed the conquest; though in private made it clear
that he was appalled, he thought that there could be (and perhaps were?) circumstances
in which the conquest would have been justified.
The pervasiveness of disagreement, and the fact that such
disagreement is necessarily entwined with important (even existential) interests
tends to make moral argument about just war appear as a form of rationalization,
and worse, as legitimating the designs of the powerful. The suspicion arises
that in trying to distinguish between justified and unjustified forms of war we
merely enable more warfare; and that
we would all be better off if the considerable intellectual energy spent on making
these distinctions were instead spent on delegitimizing warfare as such. Already
in the 16th century, when the School of Salamanca
was at the height of its influence (the Valladolid debates on
the justice of the Spanish conquest of the Americas were not just for show!) and
just war theory had evolved into a highly sophisticated discourse, there were
people who thought precisely that. In his Dulce
Bellum Inexpertis, Erasmus railed
against what he saw as the enabling role of theologians in justifying too many
wars. For him, just war reasoning was corrupting:
it turned theologians and philosophers into advocates of their patrons’
predatory projects. The correct philosophical response to the fact of warfare,
in Erasmus’ view, was not to help regulate it by articulating the principles
and rules that can justify particular wars or practices within wars, but to
deploy the full power of rhetoric to depict
the horror of warfare and to delegitimize it as much as possible. (It is worth
noting that the Dulce
Bellum Inexpertis was a sort of 16th century best seller.
The printing press was still relatively new in Europe, and Erasmus was very
good at making use of it to publicize his views).
The point is not that Erasmus thought that no war could ever be just (he does suggest here and there that some
wars could be justified), but that asking which wars are just is (most of the time) the wrong question, since
most wars will not be just. Intellectual
energy is better spent delegitimizing warfare as much as possible by depicting its
material and moral costs as vividly as possible, denouncing its general
injustice, and indicating potential alternatives. (This is implicitly an
argument about the “responsibility
of intellectuals,” though of course the point is never put that way by
Erasmus). In this way, if wars must be
fought, they will tend to be fought less often, and with more restraint; the
use of rhetoric to delegitimize warfare as such will if nothing else tend to “ratchet”
up the restrictive force of just war principles, increasing the rhetorical cost
that must be paid to start or wage a war. Whether this is in fact the case is
difficult to tell; there does seem to have been a gradual, if haphazard, “tightening”
of the restrictive force of just war principles over time, though whether this “tightening”
is at least partly due to the efforts of people like Erasmus is anybody’s guess.
For example, whereas Aquinas in the 13th century thought that almost
any “wrongdoing” that could not be redressed by the political authorities of a single
political community could constitute a just cause of war, we now treat
suspiciously any form of warfare that is not obviously defensive. And this “tightening”
of the principles of just war has been correlated (I’m not claiming causality,
however) with apparently large declines
in the overall
frequency and murderousness of war. (Yes, there are exceptions, and very
long-term trends obscure significant variation over shorter periods of time.
But the overall trends are striking, despite the greater destructiveness of modern
technologies of warfare. At any rate, one only has to read Thucydides History
of the Peloponnesian War to understand that the modern era is not particularly
inhumane in its way of waging war).
The 16th century also gave rise to a very
different response to the fact of warfare. Here the exemplary figure is Machiavelli,
and the problem is not what to do to reduce
warfare (should one help regulate it, or delegitimize it?), but how to use warfare to accomplish important
goals. Warfare is not seen as a uniquely awful experience, but as a tool of politics;
and one must study “The
Art of War,” not because one ought to avoid war, but because one must learn
to use it efficiently. Machiavelli
(among others, though he most of all) wants to study the “economy
of violence,” in Sheldon Wolin’s useful phrase, to put war to use, and in
particular to put it to use for purposes that are internal to political life (the achievement of power, the
foundation and preservation of political communities, etc.). Machiavelli’s
thought is especially original not so much because he wants to study the
economy of violence, however (there are many precedents, and Machiavelli’s
advice in this respect, though generally acute, is not always great), but
because he thinks that the standards
by which we must judge the use of violence are themselves internal to the practice
of politics: greatness rather than goodness. The point is to learn to do memorable and admirable deeds, and the most admirable deeds are those which
produce lasting authority structures (founding religions
and political communities, for example), not those that are most in keeping with conventional moral rules (or
are accomplished with the least amount of violence). (I might write more on
this point. It’s something I’ve been thinking about). But even if one disagrees with Machiavelli
that these are legitimate goals, and that reducing warfare is much more
important, one might still think that
doing so requires understanding the economy of violence and using it judiciously:
that seems to me to be the genuine moral core of “realism” as a kind of
consequentialist theory.
Though the Machiavellian response is not a direct reaction to the development of just war theory, it is nevertheless a logical response to the same concerns that led Erasmus to move away from just war reasoning. It’s interesting to me that the European experience of the
16th century produced these entirely divergent responses to war, despite the fact that all of the writers who were operating in these traditions had similar understandings of what war entailed (war was after all a very common experience in their world). None of them were especially naive about human beings and their limitations, and many had real influence with those in power. Yet these three responses seem to be fundamentally different, and the difference is not always rooted in radically different understandings of human nature (though they do differ on this point, especially Erasmus). In my class, I sometimes put the point in slogan form: just war
theory says (about war) “regulate it,” Erasmian pacifism says “delegitimize it,”
and Machiavellian political science says “study and use it.”
Yet which of these
responses is the best one? And how are they related to one another? Are they
complementary responses, such that a division of intellectual labor between
their proponents is possible, and capable of promoting important values over
time? (Just war theory and Erasmian-style pacifism do seem to me to be related
in something like this way, but to be in tension with Machiavellian political
science). Or are they ultimately incompatible, so that we must choose among
them? And does the development of just war theory typically necessarily generate,
in a “dialectical” fashion, these alternative responses to war? I suspect that
it does: as just war theory becomes more complex, it comes to seem more futile,
giving rise both to Erasmian-style “delegitimize it” responses
Machiavellian-style “study and use it” responses, and yet it never fully disappears; and
perhaps just war theory itself becomes more relevant after periods where both Erasmian
and Machiavellian responses seem to fail (perhaps the period after WWII).
[Update 9/22: fixed some typos and made some minor wording changes]
[Update 9/22: fixed some typos and made some minor wording changes]
Niebuhr wrestled with a lot of these issues. Like Erasmus, he knew that nations will use the language of justice--like just war--to pursue power, interest and prestige even though these ends are inconsistent with morality. Niebuhr's problem is that the only ones who can stop injustice, the truly moral amongst us, do not use violence as a matter of principle. Thus, those "children of darkness" run rampant, because they know those "stupid children of light" will do nothing to stop them. War is distasteful to the man of conscience, but it is worse to let evil go unchecked. It's in this way that he resembles Aquinas, because he makes a point that the means must be appropriate to the ends. What makes him different from Aquinas is that the means are judged by their effectiveness, not by some independent standard as in ius in bello. Better to use overkill and stop the evil than use some non-violent embargo that starves innocents but does nothing to overturn the unjust regime. This makes him similar to Machiavelli, but Niebuhr(unlike the other realists of the time) did not see Machiavelli as a model for realism. Augustine and his conception of the two cities was, for Niebuhr, a better model for realism.
ReplyDeleteHeard a visiting speaker recently from the US saying 'Just war is Unjust'. Perhaps war during Aquinas & Erasmus's era was all because of power & winning realms or so it seems. It seemed to have been the way they did their warring business & gaining territory. Fast-track this to contemporary period, war is still being declared for reasons known to those declaring war as in the case of War in Iraq by USA. Was it because of economic gains? or was it to show the world America is powerful & still rules the world to some degree in terms of capital & resources. I agree to the statement that 'Just War is Unjust'. This is purely that its seen to be a gain economically & giving jobs to several thousands soldiers and war materials i.e trucks, arms, equiping soldiers with guns etc. Its a money-making venture & one that spins in a viscious cycle where USA gains even though some soldiers may go back in body bags.
ReplyDeleteI also like your comment, quote " In my class, I sometimes put the point in slogan form: just war theory says (about war) “regulate it,” Erasmian pacifism says “delegitimize it,” and Machiavellian political science says “study and use it.” Realist approach says it all which is now appearing very dated.