Jay
Ulfelder kindly points his readers to my (recently updated!) working paper
on “The Irrelevance
of Legitimacy” in a
recent post where he expresses doubt about the explanatory usefulness of
the concept of legitimacy. As long-term readers will know, I am entirely in
agreement with Jay when he says that
We appeal to legitimacy when we
need to explain the persistence of political arrangements that defy our
materialist predictions, and when those arrangements do finally collapse, we
say that their failure has revealed a preceding loss of legitimacy. In statistical
terms, legitimacy is the label we attach to the residual, the portion of the
variance our mental models cannot explain. It is a tautology masquerading as a
causal force.
It occurs to me that “legitimacy” plays more or less the
same role in political science that “technology” sometimes plays in economics. Both are
residual concepts that provide an illusion of understanding but do not actually
explain much. In economics, talk of “technology” often obscures the fact that
we don’t have a very good general
theory of what explains economic growth, as Matt
Yglesias noted a couple of weeks ago:
Economists have shown that modern
economic growth can't be accounted for merely by growth in the size of the
labor force or by accumulation of additional capital. You need to add a third
element into the mix. This element is sometimes called "total factor
productivity" and sometimes called "technology," but it
represents a statistical discrepency, not an inquiry into independently
identifiable properties of technological growth. It's like Molière's doctors
explaining that opium puts people to sleep because of its virtus dormitiva.
If the discrepency were small,
this might not be a big deal and we'd say that economists had shown that
capital accumulation is the key to economic growth. But it's not small. What's
been found is that economic growth is largely unexplained. Using the word
"technology" as a label for the discrepency makes it sound as if the
issue is much better understood than it really is.
Technology is here the “Solow residual:” all the
different mechanisms by which economic growth occurs that are not accounted for by simple measures of
labor and capital utilization. But there are many such mechanisms! Education,
changes in political institutions and property rights, the invention of new
machines and business methods, new forms of economic organization, changes
in social roles, norms, and culture, etc. all can contribute to economic
growth beyond increases in labor supply and capital accumulation; but only some
of these mechanisms correspond to what we normally think about when we say “technology,”
and forgetting this is likely to lead to incorrect inferences. Moreover, we do not actually know which of these
mechanisms is the most important in general, and hence which government policies would be most likely
to increase growth.
Similarly, “legitimacy” is the label we typically use in
political science for all the factors that sustain social order or norms beyond
obvious coercion and material incentives. We all agree that the persistence of
norms and social order cannot be fully (or
even mostly) explained by crude
material incentives and obvious coercion; but by subsuming all these “other”
factors under a single label we miss the fact that they are really quite
various. Collective action problems, rational conservatism, signalling
conventions, emotional attachments, habits of discourse and conceptual blinders, identity and
affiliation entanglements, sophistry and propaganda, even sincere beliefs in
the rightness of the norms or forms of social order in question (for a detailed examination of these mechanisms, read my paper); all of these mechanisms
can contribute to their maintenance, and only some of them are close to the folk model of “legitimacy,” in which norms persist because in some sense those subject to them "like" them or at least "accept" them on their own terms. (A model that I take to be false in most relevant cases). Moreover, to the extent that we are interested in changing particular social
norms or forms of social order, we will do better to think in terms of how particular mechanisms sustain these
norms, rather than in terms of “legitimacy.”
No comments:
Post a Comment