In the closing pages of Eichmann in Jerusalem, Hannah Arendt
notoriously claimed that “politics is not like the nursery; in politics
obedience and support are the same” (p. 279). Her point was that whatever
Eichmann’s motivations or beliefs might have been ultimately, he had made
himself a “willing instrument in the organization of mass murder;” and
ethically and legally speaking, that fact
was all that mattered. To support a regime (especially a murderous one) could
be nothing more and nothing less than to act in whatever way the regime asks
you to.
There is something harsh and uncompromising
about this view. We often seem to want to distinguish between support and
obedience, or at least to excuse some forms of obedience on the grounds that such
obedience was not granted willingly or not grounded in genuine support. We
might speak of “preference falsification” and attempt to separate overt obedience, given out of fear or
lack of options or greed, from the “real” or “baseline” support that would have been given in the absence of ignorance,
coercion, peer pressure or other incentives. (I have often written in this way,
and find it a useful shorthand for thinking about things like cults
of personality). And when we think about questions of responsibility in
coercive regimes we sometimes engage in a complicated moral calculus that
balances the inculpatory force of actual obedience against the exculpatory
force of morally objectionable incentives (partially) underlying that
obedience. Here I take it that our usual intuitions indicate that negative
incentives for obedience (like threats of violence) are more exculpatory than
positive incentives (like jobs or money), and positive incentives are more
exculpatory than “intrinsic” preferences. The man who falsely denounces his
neighbour on pain of seeing his son put in prison and tortured may do a wrong,
but the wrong is partly excused by the threat of violence (perhaps he does the
lesser of two evils), whereas the man who denounces his neighbour in exchange
for money behaves less excusably (even if he really needs the money), and the
man who denounces his neighbour for fun is a simply a monster. (And what about
the man who supports a coercive system because he thinks it is the right
system? Here our intuitions seem inconsistent, or perhaps depend on what we
think about the source of the belief). In other words, we typically believe that
obedience gained at gunpoint expresses less “genuine” support than obedience
gained by an appeal to material interest, and that the most genuine support is
manifested in purely “disinterested” obedience or collaboration.
I want to put aside for a moment the moral
questions about responsibility and exculpation, and just focus on whether we
can speak about “support” independently of obedience, i.e., about some “real”
level of support underlying a person’s obedience to or collaboration with
authority. And here I think Arendt was on to something: to ask about
“real” motivations in politics is often fruitless, and sometimes positively
perverse. The only way to demonstrate support in politics is by obeying,
collaborating, or otherwise doing what the group one supports expects of you;
the demand for additional proofs of
support can only result in socially destructive (if sometimes individually
advantageous) signalling games (see here,
here,
and here
for some examples in this blog; Arendt’s favourite example was the destructive
politics of purity during the terror in
the French revolution). And the inner world of motivation and belief is too
obscure (even to the agent) and fragile to survive the light of publicity, as
Arendt repeatedly stressed.
More precisely, I am not sure that it makes
sense to speak of political support independently
of the institutions that condition obedience and collaboration. For purposes of
analysis, we can (sometimes) separate out various “inputs” of what we might
call the obedience-production function – coercion, monetary incentives, peer
pressure and so on – and call the residual “real or genuine support,” a pure
preference for collaboration with or obedience to a group or leader. This is basically
what you get in Kuran’s classic analysis of preference
falsification and its consequences, which I quite like (in fact, I use it
constantly); but it is at best a simplification of the complex phenomenology of
belief and motivation, especially when coercion and other external “incentives”
dominate over whatever “intrinsic” preferences one may care to postulate. For
one thing, in environments where coercion and other incentives are large enough,
this residual preference is itself likely to be at least partially produced by
all the other forces at work and is likely to be quite small in magnitude; and
perhaps more importantly, it won’t always make sense to speak of this residual
as a “preference” for the leader or the regime (or as a belief in its legitimacy,
for that matter).
These ideas came to mind when reading
Robert F. Worth’s superb and disturbing NY
Times piece on the last days of the Qaddafi regime:
Unlike Benghazi,
the old opposition stronghold in eastern Libya where the rebellion began in
February, Tripoli had been a relative bastion of support for Qaddafi. Even the
bravest dissidents, who risked their lives for years, often posed as smiling
backers of Qaddafi and his men. Now the masks were off, but another game of
deception was under way. At all the military bases I visited, I found soldiers’
uniforms and boots, torn off in the moments before they had, presumably,
slipped on sandals and djellabas and run back home. Even the prisoners I spoke
with in makeshift rebel jails had shed their old identities or modified them.
“I never fired my gun,” they would say. “I only did it for the money.” “I
joined because they lied to me.”
Everyone in
Tripoli, it seemed, had been with Qaddafi, at least for show; and now everyone
was against him. But where did their loyalty end and their rebellion begin?
Sometimes I wondered if the speakers themselves knew. Collectively, they
offered an appealing narrative: the city had been liberated from within, not
just by NATO’s relentless bombing campaign. For months, Qaddafi’s own officers
and henchmen had quietly undermined his war, and ordinary citizens had slowly
mustered recruits and weapons for the final battle. In some cases, with a few
witnesses and a document or two, their version seemed solid enough. Others,
like Mustafa Atiri, had gruesome proof of what they lived through. But many of
the people I spoke with lacked those things. They were left with a story; and
they were telling it in a giddy new world in which the old rules — the
necessary lies, the enforced shell of deference to Qaddafi’s Mad Hatter
philosophy — were suddenly gone. It was enough to make anyone feel a little
drunk, a little uncertain about who they were and how they got there.
Were these people deceiving themselves or
others? Did the soldiers really support
Gaddafi in the past but now do not? Do some of these people support Gaddafi still?
The question makes less sense to me than it once did. It is clear that they
once obeyed Gaddafi and now do not;
and that the change from obedience to non-obedience must be explained as a
result of a changing configuration of “inputs” to the obedience-production
function, so to speak (changing configurations of coercion, monetary
incentives, peer pressure, views of the rebels, etc.); but to attempt to
determine if, in their heart of hearts, these people supported Gaddafi then (net of all of these forces) and now do not
seems slightly absurd. Their obedience and disobedience, support and lack of
support are nothing but the vector product of all the forces
(threats of coercion, positive incentives, beliefs about Gaddafi, idiosyncratic
likes and dislikes, moral convictions, obscure and half-formed ideas about the future, etc.) operating through them. It may
make sense to attempt to disentangle these forces if we are interested in legal
or moral responsibility, or in the private tragedies of everyday life in Libya, but it does not make sense to me to attempt to figure
out if Gaddafi enjoyed some “genuine” level of support (independent of coercion, money,
etc.) as a separate explanatory factor.
But didn’t some people love Gaddafi? And
doesn’t such love make a difference? (This is basically the old “fear
and love” problem). I do not think it makes the explanatory difference it is
sometimes thought to make: those with more “love” for Gaddafi were not
necessarily those more committed to the defence of his regime, for example. Here
is another passage that jumped out at me in the piece (but really, read
it all, though some of the stories are quite disturbing):
Of all the former
Qaddafi loyalists I spoke with, only one offered a rationale that went beyond
money or compulsion. His name was Idris, and he was a handsome 21-year-old
medical student with a downy wisp of beard, a pink T-shirt and jeans. Idris (he
asked me not to use his full name) talked about Qaddafi’s loss in a baffled,
crestfallen way. We drove to a cafe not far from Algeria Square — since renamed
Qatar Square by the rebels, in deference to Qatar’s support for the Libyan
revolt — and got a table. I was amazed to see that Idris still had an image of
Qaddafi on the screen of his cellphone. “I’ve been passionate for Qaddafi ever
since I was born,” he said. His parents felt the same way, though he insisted
they had not held any position or drawn any special benefits. “Libya is just a
bunch of tribes, and there are blood feuds,” Idris said, when I asked him why.
“We see Qaddafi as the only wise man with the power to stop the feuds. If he
fails, there will be no one to mediate.” I asked what he thought of Qaddafi’s
apparent support for terrorists and his reputation as a maniac in the West. “We
see him as a brave man who speaks out against American bullying, as other Arab
leaders do not,” Idris said. “So they accuse him of these things.” Idris
conceded that Qaddafi made the mistake of surrounding himself with bloodthirsty
people like Abdullah Senussi, his security chief and brother-in-law. He also
said, like many loyalists, that he was misled about the rebels by Libyan state
television, which portrayed them as terrorists. Yet he gave no ground in his
love for Qaddafi. When I asked how he felt about Tripoli’s fall, he said:
“Devastated. It’s like someone you love, and they’re gone.”
Our conversation
began to draw interest from two men sitting at a nearby table, and Idris was
getting nervous. We got back into the car and drove to his neighborhood, Abu
Selim, a stronghold of support for Qaddafi. The neighborhood is known for
criminals and immigrants — a ready base of support for the regime — but Idris’s
area was more middle-class. As we drove down his own street, he pointed
derisively to the new rebel flags hanging outside the houses. “This was all
green flags until last week,” he said. “They love Qaddafi. They haven’t opened
their shops, everything is still closed. They are afraid.” Later, he added:
“Honestly, before February there was no such thing as pro- or anti-Qaddafi.
Only those people who were directly affected, the prisoners or the very
religious men, had any view.” We drove past the stalls of a local market,
blackened by fire in the final days of fighting. Idris gazed out sadly. “Change
is not worth this kind of destruction,” he said. On one wall, I saw the words
“Who are you?” It was a satire, like so much of the graffiti, aimed at one of
Qaddafi’s recent speeches, in which he repeatedly asked the rebels who they
were. But in this neighborhood, full of silent and resentful young men like
Idris, the words took on a very different meaning.
I think Idris inadvertently hits on a
couple of important points. First, it is interesting to note that when one
strips away all the other “inputs” to the production of support – money,
coercion, peer pressure, etc. – we are forced to speak of things like “love”
(for Qaddafi!). But this love is hardly comprehensible as a preference for
Qaddafi over the alternatives, or even as a belief in the “legitimacy” of
Qaddafi’s regime; it is obscurely wrapped up with a person’s identity and
understanding of the world, and its political
consequences appear not to have been significant. (Idris does not appear to
have fought for Qaddafi when things got tough, despite his love for him, unlike
many other people who were loyal to Qaddafi out of a variety of pragmatic
considerations of interest and fear). As a side note, I suspect that one cannot normally speak of beliefs in legitimacy except in the
Hobbesian sense of beliefs that converge on particular rules or persons as
sovereign. To believe in the legitimacy of a regime is simply to expect that other people will obey its rules and
officials and collaborate with its authority; when that expectation disappears,
so does the regime, but this is obviously very different from something that
can be measured by means of opinion polls, and it seems to have very little to
do with the personal feeling that someone like Idris might have had for Qaddafi.
Second, Idris is right to note that before
people were forced to take sides, “there was no such thing as pro- or
anti-Qaddafi. Only those people who were directly affected, the prisoners or
the very religious men, had any view.” The public act of taking a position
obviates any question of “inner” support, since the public act is a clear
signal of support. And without that public act, there is really no such
thing as pro- or anti- Qaddafi “support” other
than the ordinary collaboration of everyday life. It is only when people
are called upon to do something one
way or the other – to shoot prisoners, as some of the people whose stories are
told in the piece were called upon to do, or spy on their neighbours, or
anything that actually puts them at risk – that we can speak of support (or lack of support) in politically significant ways. And
here Arendt is obviously right: obedience and support then are the same; to support the regime was to fight for it,
whatever complex motivations one might have had for doing so. It is worth
understanding the complexity and tragedy of these motivations (the story of
Furjani, in the article, gives a glimpse of the tragic situation in which some
people are placed when coercion is the dominant input the obedience-production
technology), but from the point of view of explaining
the maintenance and fall of the regime these will add very little beyond the
obvious facts that most people supported the regime because they thought it was
in their interest to do so or were afraid to do otherwise.