A rather long post on reading the Korean Central News Agency's headlines I am not putting directly on this blog because it contains interactive graphs that I cannot figure out how to embed, but look nice on GitHub. North Korean politics plus lots of data art, including baroque Sankey flow diagrams!
See it here.
Showing posts with label North Korea. Show all posts
Showing posts with label North Korea. Show all posts
Monday, February 13, 2017
Thursday, March 13, 2014
The Varieties of Electoral Experience
(Some commentary on recent elections in North Korea, and on electoral rituals generally)
As many readers will know, North Korea just had an election for the Supreme People’s Assembly. In these elections – held more or less every five years, previously in 2009 – voters are presented with only one candidate per district, all of them belonging to the Korean Workers’ Party, and expected to vote “yes.” (Though technically they could mark “no” on their ballot papers, voting is not genuinely secret, and North Korean defectors report feeling that the risks of voting “no” are so large that practically no one does it). Even if voters had a choice, however, the offices they are voting for have no real power; as in the old Soviet joke, we might say that citizens in North Korea pretend to vote and deputies pretend to rule. (Some cynically-minded readers might say this idea applies far more widely).
One might think this would be reason enough for voters to sit out the election, but participation is not optional; though apparently some hardship dispensations are available, failure to show up to vote appears to carry severe risks, since the elections function as a political census, providing information about people who might have left the country, military personnel gone AWOL, and other undesirables that can then be used against non-voters and/or their families. New Focus International (a website run by North Korean defectors) reports:
A state powerful enough to produce these outcomes can clearly dispense with elections: the Chinese state does not hold direct elections for its highest legislative bodies, for example, despite claiming to be just as democratic as the North Korean state. Yet North Korea, like almost every other state in the world, prefers to retain public electoral rituals (and has retained them for more than fifty years; NELDA indicates that there have been 10 such elections since 1962, mostly at regular five year intervals, though with one 8 year gap between the 1990 and 1998 elections). But why bother?
One answer I’ve seen in a couple of places seems tempting, but incorrect: that these elections are meant to “legitimate” the regime by providing a “veneer” of democracy (see, e.g., here). The problem is that there is no evidence that anyone is fooled who did not already want to be fooled, and certainly not anyone with any genuine influence in the regime: not the international community (which appears to feel at best amused, at worst trolled, by the whole thing), not the leaders being “elected” (who presumably are well informed about who has real power in the regime, and know it’s not the voters), and not the voters, who “generally have no interest in who their candidate is as many already live their lives apart from the state, and don’t bother to find out the name of the person they have just ‘voted’ into office,” and who have apparently occasionally engaged in iconoclastic destruction of candidate posters and other election-related vandalism under cover of darkness. The “veneer” of democracy that North Korean elections provide is too thin to do any genuine work producing political support for the regime.
Moreover, when we look at the KCNA dispatches that talk about the feelings of voters and the meaning of the event, we find that they do not emphasize the opportunity for popular participation provided by the election, or its democratic character, but the ways in which the ritual shows the people’s unity, loyalty, and gratitude; to the extent that the elections “legitimate” the regime (or better, produce emotional attachments and normative support for the regime), not even the regime thinks that they do so by convincing them that they live in a democracy. (Even in “real” democracies people complain about the lack of choice; why would North Koreans be any different? We must have a very poor opinion of people’s political competence to believe that they can be tricked in this way.)
Though we know very little about voter behavior in North Korea, we do have some knowledge about single party elections in the Soviet Union and various Eastern European states under communist rule, and we have some more robust theories about the purpose of periodic elections and the motivations of voters in settings with some token opposition, like Mexico under the PRI from 1929 until at least 1994, Egypt under Mubarak, or Russia today. This literature suggests that elections do not serve a single purpose for all regimes, and voters behave differently across authoritarian contexts (and in turn behave differently in such contexts than in democratic contexts): the varieties of electoral experience are many. Regimes may stage overwhelming victories to send a signal of invincibility and thus to deter opposition among elites; they may encourage electoral competition to distribute spoils to elites that have some degree of social support, thus coopting these into the regime; they may use elections to determine the competence of officials in mobilizing the population, and/or to observe incipient opposition if actual turnout does not match expected turnout; and they may stage them periodically to produce an orderly circulation of elites, or as a way of managing succession problems. At the same time, voters may vote even while knowing that their vote cannot affect the composition of the government in order to receive election-day goods or to avoid potentially negative consequences; to express support or dissatisfaction (expressive voting is not confined to more democratic contexts); or even because they think it is the right thing to do. But the idea that elections serve to give “legitimacy” to the government plays almost no role in any of these theories.
Soviet elections, which are perhaps most comparable to those in North Korea, are an especially interesting case. (I draw here on a piece by Rasma Karklins from 1986). The Soviet Union spent enormous resources on electoral rituals, which were frequent (more so than in North Korea, on average one per year) and regular. There were “campaigns,” and the day of voting was a festive occasion, sometimes including ceremonies where first time voters were presented with flowers or other gifts. As in North Korea, the voter could only choose to vote “yes” or “no,” but voting “no” entailed some risk and could not be properly done secretly. As in North Korea, the regime enlisted party cadres and ordinary citizens as “agitators” to produce maximum turnout (agitators were made responsible for bringing 20-30 voters to the polls), and there was enormous social pressure to vote. All of this meant that elections always resulted in nearly unanimous verdicts – over 99% support for the party in most cases, with turnouts similarly over 97%. The efforts the regime put on achieving unanimity are remarkable, and the language used to report the results shows striking similarities to the language KCNA uses today (minus the reference to the democratic character of the Soviet Union):
More importantly, Soviet elections seem to have produced in the long run not legitimacy, but alienation. If politics involves everywhere the mobilization of emotion through ritual, the dominant emotions such rituals produced and amplified seem to have been closer to resignation rather than enthusiasm; the regime ritually triumphed over the citizens by forcing them to participate in a mass charade, boasting of its ability to get citizens to approve of it even when everybody knew of the falsity of these claims. A Soviet election in the 1970s and 80s, at least, was thus a ritual designed to lower the emotional energy of the citizens, and increase that of its rulers, though it is plausible to imagine that the ritual aspects of the elections served to produce enthusiasm in citizens early on – a Soviet election, like an election almost everywhere, was first and foremost a big party, where the symbols of the regime were the key objects of attention, and where emotional commitments to these symbols (including political parties and candidates) can be amplified and preserved (or lost and reversed). It is in this sense that an election can “legitimate” a regime (though in competitive contexts, it always does so at the expense of producing negative emotions among partisans of the losing parties, something that is never properly emphasized in accounts of how democratic elections “legitimate” states). Yet the “legitimation” involved in Soviet elections as the regime wore on was less that granted by citizens on rulers (through enthusiastic emotional attachment to regime symbols, including the party and its candidates) than a kind of self-legitimation by rulers on themselves, more and more dependent on the ability of the regime to “triumph” over its citizens by making them passive and acquiescent rather than enthusiastic and committed.
Today, I suspect that North Korean elections are similarly alienating to North Korean citizens: the people who are emotionally elevated by participation in them are more likely to be the rulers than the citizens. There is evidence that the “hidden transcript” in North Korea is different from the public narrative; that many North Koreans, like people everywhere, mock the symbols of oppressive power whenever they think can get away with it. Where voters endorse the elect, and officials elect the people they desire, the people is likely to become more and more emotionally distanced from these officials as time wears on. Yet the triumphalist ritual of such elections is still useful to rulers committed to remaining in power; the appearance of power, is power.
Update 3/13/2014: edited one passage for clarity, fixed a typo.
As many readers will know, North Korea just had an election for the Supreme People’s Assembly. In these elections – held more or less every five years, previously in 2009 – voters are presented with only one candidate per district, all of them belonging to the Korean Workers’ Party, and expected to vote “yes.” (Though technically they could mark “no” on their ballot papers, voting is not genuinely secret, and North Korean defectors report feeling that the risks of voting “no” are so large that practically no one does it). Even if voters had a choice, however, the offices they are voting for have no real power; as in the old Soviet joke, we might say that citizens in North Korea pretend to vote and deputies pretend to rule. (Some cynically-minded readers might say this idea applies far more widely).
One might think this would be reason enough for voters to sit out the election, but participation is not optional; though apparently some hardship dispensations are available, failure to show up to vote appears to carry severe risks, since the elections function as a political census, providing information about people who might have left the country, military personnel gone AWOL, and other undesirables that can then be used against non-voters and/or their families. New Focus International (a website run by North Korean defectors) reports:
At any other point in the year, family members of missing persons can get away with lying or bribing surveillance agents, saying that the person they are looking for is trading in another district’s market. But it is during an election period that a North Korean individual’s escape to China or South Korea becomes exposed.
There is much more to this election, which takes place once every five years, than politics or propaganda: it is the occasion on which the North Korean state conducts a comprehensive crackdown on missing individuals.
The number of ‘missing’ persons began to snowball around 20 years ago. During the ‘Arduous March’ of the mid 90s, when North Koreans suffered mass famine, many living in inland provinces escaped from their designated residential areas to seek survival opportunities elsewhere. The exact number of those who starved to death during this time is difficult to establish, not least because it was impossible to identify the dead bodies that constantly piled up near train stations and rivers.
As the North Korean state collected the bodies in trucks and transported them to the hills to bury en masse, it exacerbated the confusion of surveillance and security agents in their record-keeping. Although agents continued to receive daily reports from residential surveillance officers, sometimes not even the family members of the missing persons themselves could confirm whether their loved one was dead or alive.
Moreover, those who know that someone in their family has safely made it to China will keep the knowledge secret, because anyone who leaves North Korea is labeled as “a traitor of the people” by the ruling Party. Even when surveillance agents drop in on the homes of missing persons and interrogate family members about their whereabouts, they will stand up to the agents and hold their ground, maintaining that they are out to trade and have not yet returned.
In the mid-2000s, state surveillance and security agents turned to tactics of persuasion rather than confrontation alone. They requested families to give up information about missing persons by saying that they knew the person was in China, but that if he or she returned to North Korea to vote in the next election, all would be forgiven by the Workers’ Party. There were threats too: if the missing person did not return for the election, the treacherous penalty of abandoning the homeland would be paid by the remaining family members.Still, it is curious that the regime insists on associating this surveillance operation with a periodic electoral ritual, rather than merely announcing a census, which would presumably serve the same purpose. At any rate it is clear that the regime takes the electoral ritual seriously in some ways. Candidate posters are printed, agitators give talks in workplaces about the importance of the elections, and a festive atmosphere is created; and after the election is over, North Korean news agencies dutifully report turnouts above 99%, with 100% support for the KWP and its leader. (The Korean Central News Agency’s report on the results of the 2009 election and its report on the 2014 election are nearly identical). Incidentally, the reason the turnout numbers do not reach 100% is the fact that “[e]lectors on foreign tours or working in oceans could not take part in the election;” KCNA even helpfully notes that electors too old or ill to go to the polls “cast their ballots into mobile ballot boxes” which, if true, appears to show a remarkable degree of commitment on the part of the state to produce a foreordained result, when it could simply cast their ballots for them.
A state powerful enough to produce these outcomes can clearly dispense with elections: the Chinese state does not hold direct elections for its highest legislative bodies, for example, despite claiming to be just as democratic as the North Korean state. Yet North Korea, like almost every other state in the world, prefers to retain public electoral rituals (and has retained them for more than fifty years; NELDA indicates that there have been 10 such elections since 1962, mostly at regular five year intervals, though with one 8 year gap between the 1990 and 1998 elections). But why bother?
One answer I’ve seen in a couple of places seems tempting, but incorrect: that these elections are meant to “legitimate” the regime by providing a “veneer” of democracy (see, e.g., here). The problem is that there is no evidence that anyone is fooled who did not already want to be fooled, and certainly not anyone with any genuine influence in the regime: not the international community (which appears to feel at best amused, at worst trolled, by the whole thing), not the leaders being “elected” (who presumably are well informed about who has real power in the regime, and know it’s not the voters), and not the voters, who “generally have no interest in who their candidate is as many already live their lives apart from the state, and don’t bother to find out the name of the person they have just ‘voted’ into office,” and who have apparently occasionally engaged in iconoclastic destruction of candidate posters and other election-related vandalism under cover of darkness. The “veneer” of democracy that North Korean elections provide is too thin to do any genuine work producing political support for the regime.
Moreover, when we look at the KCNA dispatches that talk about the feelings of voters and the meaning of the event, we find that they do not emphasize the opportunity for popular participation provided by the election, or its democratic character, but the ways in which the ritual shows the people’s unity, loyalty, and gratitude; to the extent that the elections “legitimate” the regime (or better, produce emotional attachments and normative support for the regime), not even the regime thinks that they do so by convincing them that they live in a democracy. (Even in “real” democracies people complain about the lack of choice; why would North Koreans be any different? We must have a very poor opinion of people’s political competence to believe that they can be tricked in this way.)
Though we know very little about voter behavior in North Korea, we do have some knowledge about single party elections in the Soviet Union and various Eastern European states under communist rule, and we have some more robust theories about the purpose of periodic elections and the motivations of voters in settings with some token opposition, like Mexico under the PRI from 1929 until at least 1994, Egypt under Mubarak, or Russia today. This literature suggests that elections do not serve a single purpose for all regimes, and voters behave differently across authoritarian contexts (and in turn behave differently in such contexts than in democratic contexts): the varieties of electoral experience are many. Regimes may stage overwhelming victories to send a signal of invincibility and thus to deter opposition among elites; they may encourage electoral competition to distribute spoils to elites that have some degree of social support, thus coopting these into the regime; they may use elections to determine the competence of officials in mobilizing the population, and/or to observe incipient opposition if actual turnout does not match expected turnout; and they may stage them periodically to produce an orderly circulation of elites, or as a way of managing succession problems. At the same time, voters may vote even while knowing that their vote cannot affect the composition of the government in order to receive election-day goods or to avoid potentially negative consequences; to express support or dissatisfaction (expressive voting is not confined to more democratic contexts); or even because they think it is the right thing to do. But the idea that elections serve to give “legitimacy” to the government plays almost no role in any of these theories.
Soviet elections, which are perhaps most comparable to those in North Korea, are an especially interesting case. (I draw here on a piece by Rasma Karklins from 1986). The Soviet Union spent enormous resources on electoral rituals, which were frequent (more so than in North Korea, on average one per year) and regular. There were “campaigns,” and the day of voting was a festive occasion, sometimes including ceremonies where first time voters were presented with flowers or other gifts. As in North Korea, the voter could only choose to vote “yes” or “no,” but voting “no” entailed some risk and could not be properly done secretly. As in North Korea, the regime enlisted party cadres and ordinary citizens as “agitators” to produce maximum turnout (agitators were made responsible for bringing 20-30 voters to the polls), and there was enormous social pressure to vote. All of this meant that elections always resulted in nearly unanimous verdicts – over 99% support for the party in most cases, with turnouts similarly over 97%. The efforts the regime put on achieving unanimity are remarkable, and the language used to report the results shows striking similarities to the language KCNA uses today (minus the reference to the democratic character of the Soviet Union):
The results of the elections to the USSR Supreme Soviet and the unanimous election to the country’s supreme body of state power of the candidates of the indestructible bloc of Communists and non-Party people provide striking new evidence of the monolithic unity of the Party and the people and of the working people’s full support for the domestic and foreign policy of the CPSU [Communist Party of the Soviet Union] and the Soviet state. The elections have convincingly shown the thoroughly democratic nature of the world’s first society of developed socialism and the working people’s firm resolve to persistently strive for new successes in all sectors of communist construction. (Pravda, 7 March 1979, as quoted in Karklins, p. 451)Yet these 99% turnouts are not the whole story. The turnout numbers excluded people who were not properly registered to vote, as well as (most?) prisoners, migrants without residence permits, and people who requested absentee ballots but did not actually vote. In a number of cases, people cast voters for other people, a practice that low-level people serving in electoral commissions seem to have encouraged in order to avoid trouble with their superiors. For example, Karklins reports a funny story about how “an Estonian biologist working at Tartu State University voted not only for his wife, but also for 30 of his students, apparently because the student turnout was only around 70%, and he simply took it upon himself to take care of the”problem“.” (p. 453). Actual voter turnout seems to have been closer to 90% than to 100%, and in some of the major cities like Moscow may have reached as low at 75% in some elections; and among those who voted between 1% and 5% made use of their right to enter an election booth to cast a negative vote or to write something on the ballot. Moreover, though voters expressed fear that not voting, or voting no, would lead to trouble, actual penalties seem to have been rare, more a reflection of the generalized fear produced by earlier decades of terror than of the actual incidence of punishment for not performing their assigned roles. (Karklins reports one 1971 case in which an anti-Soviet comment in a ballot led to “an arrest and a five-year sentence in a Soviet labor camp,” though this seems to have been exceptional, not the rule; and I vaguely remember something from I think Gulag Archipielago in which a single spoiled ballot during the Great Terror led to a huge search and numerous arrests). Nevertheless, these small risks meant that non-voters (and people who actually voted no) were among the more educated and politically aware USSR citizens, those most likely to dissent or emigrate; non-voting was one of the “weapons of the weak.” So when I read the North Korean numbers I wonder about the actual incidence of non-voting, especially given the fact that many North Koreans have in fact begun to live their lives “away from the state” since the famine of the 1990s; and I wonder about the actual numbers of “no” voters (are there no North Koreans who take advantage of their right to strike a candidate as a political act? Is the North Korean state so efficient at repression that it always pursues such people?); but I suspect that if the North Korean state knows such numbers, it keeps them very much secret, as they are more useful indicators of its actual support levels.
More importantly, Soviet elections seem to have produced in the long run not legitimacy, but alienation. If politics involves everywhere the mobilization of emotion through ritual, the dominant emotions such rituals produced and amplified seem to have been closer to resignation rather than enthusiasm; the regime ritually triumphed over the citizens by forcing them to participate in a mass charade, boasting of its ability to get citizens to approve of it even when everybody knew of the falsity of these claims. A Soviet election in the 1970s and 80s, at least, was thus a ritual designed to lower the emotional energy of the citizens, and increase that of its rulers, though it is plausible to imagine that the ritual aspects of the elections served to produce enthusiasm in citizens early on – a Soviet election, like an election almost everywhere, was first and foremost a big party, where the symbols of the regime were the key objects of attention, and where emotional commitments to these symbols (including political parties and candidates) can be amplified and preserved (or lost and reversed). It is in this sense that an election can “legitimate” a regime (though in competitive contexts, it always does so at the expense of producing negative emotions among partisans of the losing parties, something that is never properly emphasized in accounts of how democratic elections “legitimate” states). Yet the “legitimation” involved in Soviet elections as the regime wore on was less that granted by citizens on rulers (through enthusiastic emotional attachment to regime symbols, including the party and its candidates) than a kind of self-legitimation by rulers on themselves, more and more dependent on the ability of the regime to “triumph” over its citizens by making them passive and acquiescent rather than enthusiastic and committed.
Today, I suspect that North Korean elections are similarly alienating to North Korean citizens: the people who are emotionally elevated by participation in them are more likely to be the rulers than the citizens. There is evidence that the “hidden transcript” in North Korea is different from the public narrative; that many North Koreans, like people everywhere, mock the symbols of oppressive power whenever they think can get away with it. Where voters endorse the elect, and officials elect the people they desire, the people is likely to become more and more emotionally distanced from these officials as time wears on. Yet the triumphalist ritual of such elections is still useful to rulers committed to remaining in power; the appearance of power, is power.
Update 3/13/2014: edited one passage for clarity, fixed a typo.
Sunday, January 01, 2012
The Complexity of Emotion in Authoritarian States
Seeing the videos of crying North Koreans after the
death of Kim Jong-il, many people gravitate to the question of whether the
emotion on display there is “genuine.” As I’ve written before, I think this question misses the
point: to the extent that cults of personality matter politically (that is, secure ongoing commitments to a regime and
its institutions), the genuineness of emotion hardly matters (though it doesn’t
hurt). Cults of personality work precisely by making it very hard for
people not to provide credible signals of commitment to a political leader (including,
if necessary, proper public mourning when they die, complete with sufficient displays
of crying and rending of garments). And North Korea is not a place where people
who do not feel the requisite emotions
can safely stay home, much less display unapproved emotions in unapproved ways.
If nothing else, the inminban (neighborhood
committee: like your nosy neighbors, only superempowered to snoop on you) will
note your uncooperative and recalcitrant disposition, and then you may be
passed over for job opportunities or promotions (especially important in
relatively prosperous Pyongyang, where most of the videos are coming from); your family
may encounter difficulties in securing educational opportunities and various
material goods (the state, after all, controls most of these opportunities);
and of course you (and your family) may be punished in a variety of ways,
depending on how severe your “lack of respect” for the late and dear leader is
judged to be. [Update 15 January 2012: via Doug Mataconis, I learn that people are in fact being punished for insufficient mourning, as expected].
Under the circumstances, a bout of competitive crying (helpfully
encouraged here and there by zealous supporters or genuinely distressed people)
is a relatively low price to pay to be left alone; and there is some evidence that
at least some people engaged in this sort of strategic mourning the last time
North Korea had a leadership transition, when Kim Il-Sung died (as I discussed
at the
end of this post, on the basis of some anecdotes presented in Barbara
Demick’s fantastic Nothing to Envy). But of course by participating
in the official ritual of mourning regardless of your “sincere” feelings you
confuse everyone around you, including, it must be noted, supposedly “well-informed”
North Korea watchers. How could you possibly tell who might not feel genuinely sad (outside a
very small circle of close family members, perhaps), when everyone around you
seems to be crying so hard about the death of the leader, and the state
broadcasts carefully chosen images that suggest that the entire nation is in shock
and mourning? (Note how few images from cities like Chongjin have been
shown, where people are far less privileged than the residents of Pyongyang, have
more access to news and information coming across the border from China, and where
anti-Kim feeling is not entirely unknown). Natural cognitive biases (the “availability
heuristic,” for example) and social cues all conspire to tell the
disaffected that they are alone in their indifference or hatred for the recently
departed; in fact, they tell them that their very feelings must be mistaken, and that they better get the right kind
of feelings, pronto. Could you, dear reader, remain sulkily at home
in these circumstances, with no certainty of receiving any support from anybody
should you get in trouble with the authorities, just to make a statement? If
so, you are probably made of sterner stuff than most.
Incidentally, it is worth noting that crying convincingly is
not that hard to do, especially in groups, though it seems as if only genuinely distressed people could manage it. Like
yawning or laughing, crying is often contagious, and just as groups of people
often laugh
hard and genuinely at unfunny jokes, groups of people can cry
hard and genuinely for reasons that have little to do with “real” grief. Funeral
practices in many nations often include or have included groups of mourners who
are expected, sometimes even paid, to engage in ostentatious displays of grief
that may be far out of proportion to the sentiments of those present, and
that at any rate amplify whatever actual feelings of grief others may be experiencing.
As some
have noted, funeral attendance (accompanied by appropriate displays of
emotion) is an important part of Korean cultural norms, indicating respect for
the dead; flattery
inflation can take care of the rest. And even if you are not directly ordered to cry, “spontaneous” sorrow is
a useful signal to express in these circumstances, and the appropriate language
for expressing such sorrow is known to all in North Korea, and helpfully
reinforced by state propaganda. (This includes the knowledge of where to congregate,
what to bring, what to wear, etc.)
Nevertheless, the question of whether the people being shown
in those videos are actually feeling
distress and sadness is understandable. In many social situations, the
genuineness of emotion really matters to us,
and the possibility that North Koreans genuinely cared for Kim Jong-il makes us
uneasy. It suggests that people can be easily “brainwashed,”
in this case to care for a man who, by almost any objective measure, made their
lives much worse than otherwise, in
fact actively harmed them by his rule.
North Koreans are certainly exposed to much propaganda claiming that their leader
has godlike powers, and have often great difficulty in accessing alternative sources of information. (It is not,
however, impossible for them to access such information, especially since the
90s, and many people, especially in places close to the Chinese border, appear
to have done so). The North Korean propaganda agencies have long experience in creating
narratives of national resentment that deflect responsibility for outcomes from
leaders onto outsiders, and these narratives appear to resonate at some level
with many people in the DPRK. Indeed, sometimes their claims are even minimally
plausible: the US and other powers do bear some responsibility for North Korea’s
current state, and the atrocities of the Korean War were not all (or even
mostly) committed by communist forces. It is but a short step from here to the
thought that in this sort of information environment most people are likely to believe special claims about the Kim
family, and hence are likely to have
felt genuine grief at Kim Jong-il’s passing. Our folk-psychological ideas postulate
a simple connection between information, belief and emotion, and hence suggest
a quick “fix” for this situation: change the information environment and you change
the emotion; change the emotion and you change the regime (eventually). Yet I
think emotion in highly authoritarian contexts is a much more complex matter.
It is not even clear what “genuine” emotion could possibly mean here.
Consider, to fix ideas, a context where belief, emotion, and
action are all aligned. Here, reports of belief (saying “I love so and so” if
asked whether you love so and so), displays and signs of emotion (including the
appropriate physiological reactions at the mention of so and so’s name), and
actions (voting for so and so, giving them gifts, etc.) are all consistent with
one another: we do not observe discrepancies between what people say (even to
themselves) and what they feel or do. We might say that people in such contexts
exhibit pragmatic consistency.
Pragmatic consistency is not always achievable even in settings
where the costs of exit
are low. We are not necessarily consistent in everything we say, feel, and do, for reasons having to do with
everything from fears of social exclusion to an inability to figure out which
actions are actually consistent with our beliefs (consider the epistemic
difficulties involved in identifying what counts as the “environmentally
friendly” thing to do in particular circumstances), or which of our beliefs are
actually consistent (if nothing else, computational complexity considerations
prevent us from always identifying such inconsistencies). We sometimes even speak
of “integrity” when we sense that the achievement of pragmatic consistency is
uncommon in some context: the person of integrity is the person who can achieve consistence in belief, emotion, and action, even when such achievement is difficult. Yet the ideal of pragmatic
consistency makes it possible to speak meaningfully of “genuine” emotion –
emotion that aligns with our beliefs and actions. (By contrast, we tend to
understand signs of emotion that do not align
sufficiently with beliefs and actions as indicating ersatz emotion).
We constantly strive for pragmatic consistency, sometimes by
dubious means: we manage cognitive dissonance by discarding inconvenient
beliefs, avoid information that might threaten cherished values or that increases our anxiety, rationalize
our choices in various ways, regret actions that are too obviously inconsistent
with what we tell ourselves or our loved ones, etc. This is complicated by the
fact that we appear to have deeply rooted biases towards
interpreting the status quo as just, and that these “system justification”
motivations may conflict with “ego justification” (self-image) and “group
justification” (group identity) motivations. In any case, the greater the
dissonances to be managed, and the greater the costs of exiting a context, the
harder the achievement of pragmatic consistency, and the less meaningful talk
of genuine emotion becomes.
States like North Korea induce enormous cognitive and
emotional dissonances, despite their large degree of control over the
information environment: they claim that there is “nothing to envy” and that
the nation is “most prosperous” while offering hunger and decaying
infrastructure; they claim that the leader loves you while threatening the most
horrendous punishment if you fail to obey the slightest arbitrary rule; they tell
you to be proud of the nation while constantly discouraging all real comparisons;
they blame all bad outcomes on outsiders, and all good outcomes on insiders; they
proclaim freedom while restricting it in myriad ways, and so on. (In fairness,
such claims are not only made in
authoritarian states; but the dissonances are more obvious there). Achieving
pragmatic consistency under circumstances that involve high exit costs and
credible threats of punishment for failing to say, feel, or do particular
things is very hard; it is hardly
surprising that those who merely say what they think in such contexts often appear
as heroes of integrity – the Havels and Solzhenitsyns of
Soviet times, for example.
Managing these cognitive and emotional dissonances sometimes requires ignoring or
reinterpreting inconvenient information (e.g., most people in the GDR were able to watch West German TV, but did
not necessarily change their behavior in response to it); blaming the Tsar's ministers rather than the Tsar for bad outcomes; rationalizing the status quo in various ways; and so on. But just as cognitive dissonance can
induce belief adjustment in either direction (and hence "providing" North Koreans with more information will not necessarily imply that they will revolt), emotional dissonance can induce emotional adjustment in either direction:
one can learn to feel the required emotions in order to avoid the anxiety of not feeling the right emotions.
(One should not underestimate the human capacity for self-deception). Imagine
what not feeling the approved
emotions might entail in the North Korean case: negatively evaluating one's own country; feeling ashamed of it; feeling duped; feeling betrayed; feeling despair at the magnitude of the errors committed in the past; feeling unable to have pride in the achievements of one's community.
Some people are capable of living with such feelings without falling into deep
depression; most people, I suspect, compensate by aggressively chauvinistic
nationalism and other strategies. (“Sour
grapes,” for example).
But, precisely because such emotions are formed under a
distinct kind of pressure, they cannot
be easily interpreted as a guide to what might happen when conditions change – when exit costs
are lowered, or collective action suddenly becomes possible, and so on. Those
who cried the loudest and most “genuinely” at the death of the leader are not necessarily
those who are most likely to defend the regime if conditions were to change;
there is in fact surprisingly little evidence that the people who are most “emotionally
invested” are always the most likely to defend a regime in times of crisis. (Defenders are
typically found among those who have obvious material stakes in the regime, or who clearly stand to lose status). In
other words, the crying of thousands is not a meaningful
guide to what the people of North Korea would
say, feel, or do under conditions more conducive to pragmatic consistency.
(Happy new year everyone!)
[Update 2 January 2012: added "in times of crisis" to the last paragraph, the bit about the good Tsar to the next to last paragraph, and fixed some grammatical problems]
[Update 2 January 2012: added "in times of crisis" to the last paragraph, the bit about the good Tsar to the next to last paragraph, and fixed some grammatical problems]
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)