Stories about what makes democracy stable tend to take one
of two forms. The first stresses socialization, learning, and the gradual
development of norms of tolerance for political opposition and alternation in
power. On this view, stability usually comes with time, and the breakdown of
democracy is
to
be explained primarily by reference to cultural and normative deficits: corrupt
socialization, the emergence or widespread acceptance of anti-democratic ideologies,
the weakness of democratic norms of tolerance, and the like. In its simplest
form, this view suggests that democracy fails due to a lack of a proper
“democratic culture” and/or “inexperience” with democratic institutions. The
second kind of story, by contrast, stresses the strategic relationships among major
collective actors, like political parties, the military, the government, and
foreign powers. On this view, stability emerges only when
democracy is a
self-enforcing equilibrium (
ungated),
that is, when all actors find that supporting democratic institutions is their
“best response” to the actions of everyone else in light of their own interests, and its breakdown
is to be explained primarily by reference to the changing interests and
expectations of these actors.
These two types of stories are not wholly incompatible, to
be sure: norms can be strategically undermined and manipulated, and an
organization’s view of its interests is typically shaped, even constituted, by
whatever shared values its members have been socialized into. Strategic
equilibria may only be achievable after a period of learning, and the resulting
strategic configurations may crystallize into norms. Yet scholars of
democratization typically fall on one or the other side of this divide, and the
differing stresses they place on normative vs. strategic considerations when
explaining the stability or fragility of democracy have important practical implications.
Jay Ulfelder’s
Dilemmas of Democratic Consolidation: A
Game-Theory Approach falls squarely on the “strategic” side of the
divide. (Full disclosure: I don’t know Jay personally, but he’s a virtual
acquaintance. I enjoy
reading
his blog and
interacting with
him online; I have linked to his work before, and he has returned the favour. And while I was writing this post, he cheerfully answered my ignorant questions about his data and models).
Jay identifies three actors as especially relevant to the
stability of democracy: the incumbent government (and its key constituencies), opposition
forces, and the military. (One might have included foreign powers as well, as
some people
with
similar models of democratic stability do, but simplicity is a virtue in
game-theoretic approaches, and anyway the basic framework can easily be
extended in that way). The importance of the first two actors is clear:
democracy (in a minimal sense, at least; more on this in another post) survives
when the government is willing to yield control of the state apparatus to the
opposition when it loses an election (it prefers to yield power rather
than stage an
autogolpe or engage in
fraudulent electoral practices), and when the opposition is not tempted to overthrow
the government by extra-legal means if it is unable to win an election. The military
has independent importance in this framework because, if the government faces
substantial opposition mobilization, the military is likely to be the only
actor with sufficient organizational capacity to repress it. But this
capability, of course, introduces a familiar problem: if the military can repress
the opposition, why wouldn’t it overthrow the government as well? A cultural or
normative explanation of military self-restraint would stress the development
of a particular military culture (professionalism, a strict norm of
civilian supremacy); and while such an explanation is certainly part of a
sociologically complete answer (even though I do not in general find it
convincing), a strategic understanding of motivation suggests that given
sufficient incentives, all norms break. One must explain the self-restraint of not
only the military but of all relevant actors – their willingness to respect whatever
norms of political competition structure the political system – at least partly
in terms of how respecting these norms is strategically appropriate for them
given their interests (regardless of how these interests come to be constituted
in the first place, a question which we leave aside for the moment). If the
“best response” (in terms of the protection of their interests) of at least
some of these actors to the actions of others is to
defect from the norms of political competition, then democracy will
not survive. Democratization
is
not like growing up: democracy can fail even after long experience, if the
key actors involved find that in order to protect their important interests
their best response to the actions of others is to undermine it.
Given this basic framework, two important questions emerge.
First, we would want to know how different regimes affect the interests of
particular actors, and how these actors in turn come to understand the ways in
which different regimes affect these interests. An answer to this question
tells us how the “preferences” of different groups for different kinds of
democratic and non-democratic regimes come to be structured, and indicates what
factors can change their evaluation of the available possibilities. Jay glosses over this question perhaps too quickly, speaking simply of the “material”
interests of the various actors under different regimes, even though his own
case narratives later in the book suggest that other kinds of interests – status
interests, for example – are also quite important.
(Militaries seem to understand their interests in terms of status, in particular). At any rate, the model he develops assumes that the
preferences for particular regimes of the key collective actors will vary
depending on whether there is open political competition for power, and on whether or not they
or their allies are in control of the state. Whatever the regime type, the
benefits that come from controlling the state (or having one’s allies control
the state) will be partly offset by the expected costs of losing power, though
these prospects will differ between regime types; at least in theory, the
average costs of losing power in a democracy will tend to be smaller than the
costs of losing power in an autocracy, but the probability of losing power
might seem to be larger in a democracy (and conversely, for opposition forces, the
probability of attaining power might
seem to be smaller in an autocratic regime). Changes in the expected benefits
of holding power (or having one’s allies hold power) and/or the expected costs
of losing it (or having one’s allies lose it) will thus affect the evaluation
of different regime types, and hence the preferences of actors for different
regime types. Big oil booms or busts in petrostates, changes in the ethnic
composition of a population or in the prevalence of identity voting, the
availability of rents to allies of the opposition and the government, expected
cuts to military budgets or threats to territorial integrity, are all among the sorts
of things that should have an impact on whether relevant collective actors
prefer democracy to autocracy (and on whether they prefer the opposition or the
military to be in control in their disfavoured options). Incidentally, here we have a potential explanation for the fact (documented in the book)
that democracy tends to last longer in richer countries: to the extent that
poorer countries have more rent-driven economies (economies where wealth
depends primarily on control of political power), the costs of losing power
will be proportionately larger for the government, and the probability of
attaining power proportionately smaller for the opposition, leading to greater
incentives to “defect” on all sides - to undermine democracy if you are the government, or to attempt extra-legal seizures of power if you are not.
Second, we want to know what
parameters determine whether an actor thinks their best response to
the actions of others in light of their interests should be to support
democracy or to attempt to undermine it (“stage a coup,” for simplicity),
given a set of preferences over regime
types. Using a “
reduced
form” game theoretical model, Jay suggests that the relevant parameters are
the degree of
uncertainty about the
preferences of other actors for different regime types, and their
capacities to pull off a coup. (Jay
actually distinguishes between the coordination costs of different actors and
their capacity for pulling off a coup; but these seem to be entangled with one
another, since a collective actor’s capabilities to pull off a coup are greatly
influenced by its coordination costs, and it might have simplified his model to
have a single parameter summarizing the combined effect of both technical capabilities
and costs of coordination.) Generally speaking, the government and the military
should have greater capacities to undermine democracy than opposition forces,
since the latter are (by definition) shut out from power; and indeed of the 195
episodes of democracy in the 1955-2007 period that Jay identifies, fully 27%
ended via “executive coup” (a shorthand
for all the ways in which sitting incumbents can undermine political
competition, from the quick
autogolpe of a Fujimori
to the more
drawn-out
dismantling of the independence of all institutions of a Chavez or Putin),
21% via classic military coup, and only 2.6% via opposition-led rebellion (44%
survived beyond 2007, and about 5% ended in other ways, such as via foreign intervention
or the splitting of the country). Nevertheless, militaries and governments are
not always capable of pulling off coups due to organizational disarray or other
divisions (as in Ukraine in the early 2000s, a case discussed in the book, when
the bits of the Soviet army that became the Ukrainian army were in no position
to stage a coup despite consistent government attempts to cut its budget and
privileges), and opposition forces sometimes have access to considerable
resources (e.g., during the
coup
attempt against Chavez in 2002 the main television stations were in
the hands of opposition forces); and capacities can change, sometimes abruptly.
(In general, while technical capacities are relatively stable, costs of
coordination are
not constant or
wholly under the control of the relevant forces;
relatively insignificant events can
suddenly lower or raise them, as when a man setting himself on fire in
Tunisia catalyzed protests and collective action that continues to this day. To
speak of a “costs of coordination” parameter is merely to summarize a wide
array of factors that affect the capacities of groups to engage successfully in
risky collective action, a point that I don’t think is sufficiently stressed in
the book).
The question of uncertainty is more complicated. Jay argues
that even if every relevant collective force prefers democracy, given enough
uncertainty about the intentions and capacities of other actors, particular
groups may still wish to “strike first” to avoid being dominated by others,
regardless of their capacities. If the opposition thinks the government is trying to set up a dictatorship (even if
this is not the intention) it may feel that its interests would be better
protected by staging a preemptive coup, even
if its first preference would be for a democratic regime (this was arguably
the case in the 2002 coup against Chavez, as the book notes, though I should
note that some of the leaders of the coup might in fact have preferred an
autocratic regime). This naturally raises the question of how different actors
can credibly signal commitment to a
democratic regime, something that is a bit underexplored in the book. For one
thing, signals of commitment to democracy are partly tied to changes in
capabilities to undermine it: saying that one supports democracy is less
credible when one is busy building up ethnic armies, as Jay discusses in the case
of the breakdown of democracy in Cyprus in the 1960s. (Oddly, this case does not appear in the dataset in the appendix). Indeed, uncertainty can
be induced by well-meaning “democracy aid” that appears to change the relative
capacities of actors. For example, aid to democracy-promoting NGOs may make the
government feel more threatened by
opposition forces, and hence more
likely to undermine electoral institutions and harass such organizations in
order to prevent a later loss of power (as appears to have been the case, in
part, in Russia after the “color revolutions” of the 2000s).
Perhaps the most interesting section of the book is its
critique of democracy promotion as a way of "consolidating" democracy. Drawing on
work
by Carothers, Jay argues that much democracy promotion is insufficiently
sensitive to the strategic implications of particular interventions, and too
wedded to functionalist assumptions about the proper “components” of democracy.
(Some of the arguments here echo
Bill Easterly’s critique
of development assistance, especially the points about the difficulties
of evaluating a lot of “democracy promotion” activities, our lack of
knowledge about important aspects of the democratization process, the
bureaucratic incentives to measure the effectiveness of democracy promotion by
inputs rather than outputs, and the tendency to disregard the wider strategic
effects of these interventions on the domestic politics of the target country). It is too easy to give money for “civil
society” (in fact, the availability of such money will usually stimulate the
creation of organizations with high-sounding names but dubious democratic
credentials); it is much more difficult to manage a delicate strategic
situation so that all actors end up signalling credible commitments to
democratic norms. The book’s framework suggests that investments in
institutions that guarantee credibility (like election observation missions,
the judiciary, and electoral commissions) are thus better than direct aid to opposition
forces or “civil society” promotion in fragile democracies.
Now for some (small) critique. Aside from some quantitative
evidence, Jay uses various case studies of democratic breakdown – in Ukraine,
Fiji, Cyprus, Venezuela, and Thailand – and survival – in Spain – to illustrate
the explanatory power of the basic model. Basically, what he does is to show
how if we look at the parameters that the model indicates are “interesting” –
the apparent costs and benefits of different regimes for the relevant actors,
their signals of commitment to democracy, and their (changing) capacities for
staging coups – we can construct narratives that shed light on the process of
breakdown (or survival). Despite the fact that I am basically inclined to
believe the strategic model of democratization, I confess I was not always
entirely convinced by the interpretation of events in these narratives. For
example, in the case of Venezuela it appears that the undermining of electoral
competition occurred
during
a boom in oil prices, which increased the government’s capacity for subverting
democracy, whereas Jay stresses the previous period of stagnation (which did,
to be sure, loosen the commitment of various actors to democracy, and led to a
number of unsuccessful coup attempts). And while the narrative Jay constructs
can certainly be adjusted to account for this, it may be
too easily adjustable, and one may need
a clearer picture of how interests are affected by different kinds of regimes
to make it fully convincing. (Including
status considerations: the demand for
respect was an important ingredient in the rise of Chavez, for example).
Moreover, the evidence presented does not always
sufficiently establish how important strategic considerations are relative
to alternative explanations stressing norms, learning, and the like. Consider,
for example, figure 3.4 from the book:
The figure represents the estimated proportion of
democracies that survive after
n years since their founding elections (the "
Kaplan-Meier" estimate); the dotted red lines indicate
that about half of all democracies last 15 years or less. (The dotted black
lines represent the 95% confidence interval). Clearly, most democracies don’t
last long; but the curve does
not seem
to indicate that longer-lasting democracies have a relatively constant risk of
breakdown (which is what one would expect from a purely strategic model). If
learning and other “cultural” considerations were really important, should one
expect a slower decay process, or not? (I’m not actually sure). What one would
like to know, among other things, is how likely it is that a democracy breaks
down
given that it has lasted n years,
a quantity I would not know how to estimate (and perhaps cannot be cleanly
estimated). Similarly, Jay shows that democracies seem to last longer in
Eurasia and Latin America than in Africa – by quite substantial margins – but
it is unclear that the parameters identified by the model can account for this
difference, and the basic survival curves seem at least consistent with various
“cultural” stories. Or consider the following figure, which I’ve produced using
the data in the appendix (it's not actually in the book):
If I haven’t made any obvious mistakes, the figure suggests
that most democracies last longer on their later attempts than on their first
attempt. (So Egypt and Tunisia are not likely to end democratic 10 years from
now, even if they manage a relatively successful transition now, but might have better luck in a later attempt). But given the
book’s model, this is puzzling: why is there a “learning” effect at all? Why
should the strategic situation “improve” on the second attempt at democracy?
It is also interesting to look at countries that have had lots of democratic spells (and hence
lots of breakdowns). From the data in the book, 9 countries have had 4 or more
“spells” of democracy: Greece, Argentina, Syria, Peru, Turkey, Ghana, Peru,
Sierra Leone, and Ecuador (Argentina is the world champion, with 7 spells and 6 breakdowns). Why have democratic regimes in these countries been so
unstable? From the model in the book, one would expect that some features of
the state would either impose major costs on some actors if they accepted democracy;
make their capacities to undermine it (or demand it) fluctuate widely; and/or make
it difficult for credible commitments to democracy to be sustained (leading to
a great degree of uncertainty about the intentions of major actors). Are these
features especially pronounced in these countries, relative to others? Or is
the degree of political conflict over regimes in these countries to be
explained in other ways? Inquiring minds want to know.
Anyway, I enjoyed the book and recommend it to anyone
interested in democratization. Also, if you have made it this far you should definitely
read
Jay’s blog.
[Update 1/26/2012: a few minor stylistic adjustments]