(Continuing an occasional series on the history of political regimes. Lots of charts and graphs, and one slideshow, using the Political Institutions and Political Events dataset by Adam Przeworski et al., which is a fantastic resource for people interested in this topic. And I like pictures!).
People sometimes do not realize how total has been the normative triumph of some of the ideas typically associated with democracy, even if one thinks that democracy itself has not succeeded quite as spectacularly. Take, for instance, the norm that rulers of states should be selected through some process that involves voting by all adults in society (I'm being deliberately vague here) rather than, say, inheriting their position by succeeding their fathers. In 1788 there were only a couple of countries in the world that could even claim to publicly recognize something remotely like this norm. Most people could not vote, and voting was not generally recognized as something that needed to happen before rulers could rule; rulers could and did claim to have authority to rule on other grounds. Norms of hereditary selection structured the symbolic universe in which political competition took place, and defined its ultimate boundaries for most people (at least those who lived in state spaces). Yet by 2008 there were only four or five countries in the world that did not publicly acknowledge universal voting rights:
Tuesday, September 11, 2012
Friday, August 24, 2012
Impossible Political Systems: Further Adventures in Rawlsian Constitutional Design
I am somewhat amazed, now that I think of it, that no
“serious” political philosopher I know of has ever proposed an electoral system
like the one I proposed in this
post last week, where individual voting power is inversely proportional to
income. (By all means enlighten me if anyone has proposed something like it; I would be delighted to know. I’m
pretty certain that among the many forgotten pamphleteers of the 19th
century someone must have come up with a similar idea but I don’t have the
knowledge to locate these potentially existing antecedents). This probably
means that it is a bad idea (and judging by the few reactions I got, most
people think so); but if it is a bad idea, I would like to explore in more
detail the reasons why it is bad, since it is not obvious to me that a system
like that would not meet Rawls’
principles of justice.[1]
(And I sort of would like to see a few more responses).
A recap: I suggested (more or less tongue in cheek) that
Rawls’ difference principle could potentially be met by a political system
where everyone has a vote, but the formal value of your vote declines the more
you earn. There are a number of different ways of achieving this, but the most
interesting (at least to me!) version of this system is the following.
We divide voters into n
income (or wealth) equal classes (or quantiles). Voters in the first (poorest)
class have median income y and a
single vote each, whereas voters in the nth (richest) class have median income any (that is, the median
income of the richest class is a times
the median income of the poorest class) and 1/anx
votes each, where x is a number
between 0 and 1 that determines the extent of the “disenfranchisement” of high
income voters. “Income” here is post-tax, post transfer income.[2]
The value of a person’s vote thus depends on their income class; more
specifically, it is inversely proportional to the ratio between the median income
of their class and the median income of the poorest class. For n > 1, if x = 0 then every voter
has one vote, and the system reduces to the normal “one person, one vote” system;
if x = 1 then the extent of rich
voter disenfranchisement is strictly proportional to the average income of
their income class, so a voter in the kth
income class would have 1/ak votes.
A numerical example may be useful. Imagine that this system had
been in place in the USA in 2008, with x
= 1 (so the value of the votes of the richer classes is strictly inversely
proportional to their income), and n = 10
(so there are ten classes of voters). According to the Luxembourg
Income Study, the income ratio between the bottom and the top decile of the
income distribution in the USA in 2010 was 6.154 (so a10=6.154). In this imaginary political system, in other
words, the poorest decile of the income distribution would have had about six
times the voting power of the highest decile. About 75% of these people voted
democratic in the 2008 congressional elections, according to the American
National Election Study, whereas only about 33% of the people in
the highest income decile did so. A very quick and dirty simulation (see code and explanation here)
suggests that if this system had been in place in 2008, the Democratic party
would have won about 62% of the two-party vote (61% if we assume turnout rates
would have stayed the same, with poorer voters voting at lower rates than
richer voters), rather than the 54% that it actually won – an 8% difference,
which one imagines would have been translated into somewhat different policies.
A system like this would thus have amplified the influence of the
bottom decile of the income distribution (and of the lower half of the income distribution generally), though
of course parties would have behaved very differently in the new environment,
so the example is merely illustrative. (A simulation for New Zealand is a bit
harder to do given our different electoral system and my inability to use the NZ
Election Study, but I’d love to see one).
Note that we could in principle consider systems where x > 1 or x < 0, though I doubt such regimes would pass Rawlsian muster.
If x is much greater than 1, the
votes of the richer classes are discounted very quickly: with a small number of
classes (say n = 4) we then get a “dictatorship
of the proletariat”; with a larger number of classes and a very large value for
x, we get basically a simple dictatorship
of the very poorest people in society. Similarly, if x > 0 and the number of classes is small, we get a régime censitaire, where the rich have more formal voting power than the poor
(like the Roman republic of Cicero’s time); if x is much smaller than -1
and the number of classes is large we simply get a dictatorship of the richest
people in society.
Note also that if n = 1
then the system reduces to the usual "one person, one vote" system; for n = 2 voters below the median income
each get one vote, while voters above the median income each get
votes, where a2 is the ratio of the average income of voters above
the median income to the average income of voters below the median income; and
so on. The smaller n, the more abrupt
differences in voting power are (though they are ultimately less steep),
whereas the larger n, the more gradual and steeper the
differences in voting power. So, for n =
2, the superrich end up with the same voting power as the middle class, and
the lower middle class ends up with the same voting power as the very poorest,
though the poor and the lower middle class end up with more voting power than
the upper middle class and the rich; for n
= 100, the superrich end up with much less
voting power than the middle class, but the middle class in turn ends up
with less voting power than the very poorest, even though voters in adjacent
income classes end up having similar voting power. If n is high but x is close
to zero we have smooth differences in voting power but a small gradient, so
that rich and poor end up having similar voting power per person but there are
many small gradations. All of this would be easier to show in a simple
interactive simulation (a Mathematica notebook, perhaps?) with a couple of sliders
for n, x, and some choice of potential income distributions, but that is
beyond my ability to do right now; for now, all I can offer is some R code here if
people want to play with various choices of parameters.
So how should we choose the parameters n and x? Current voting
systems in democracies at least pay lip service to the idea that each elector
is formally equal, i.e., that n should
be 1 and x should be 0, even if in
practice the value of some voters’ votes is larger than the value of others. (In
elections to the US senate, the million or so Montana citizens have about 37
times the voting power of the 37 million or so California citizens, a ratio that is
much higher than the ones contemplated in the numerical example of this system
above. this is an approximation - I should look up the actual numbers of voters, not just the populations - but it will do for a ballpark figure). But would a person choose these exact parameters for an electoral
system from behind a veil of ignorance? Rawls himself notes
that one must evaluate political institutions by their tendency to produce just
outcomes (they are forms of “imperfect procedural justice,” like jury trials);
and it is not clear that n = 1 and x = 0 yield the most just outcomes. And
the advantages, from a Rawlsian point of view, of choosing larger values for
both n and x seem considerable.
Most people (including
Rawls) would say that the rich have more influence than the poor in politics,
influence that is disproportionate to their numbers (though not everyone thinks
this is a bad thing). The reasons are obvious. Standing for elections costs
money, and the need for financing campaigns from moneyed private interests may
push certain issues to the forefront of the public agenda, and make others invisible.
The rich can lobby representatives more easily, and have more ability to
coordinate and spread their ideas than the poorest. In the USA, Martin Gilens
has argued
that the views of the poor have almost
no influence on the actions of their representatives when
these views diverge from those of the rich. To be sure, not all of these
things are necessarily negative. The ability of the rich to lobby can be
construed as an informational subsidy to legislators. If the rich are better
informed than the poor, policy that is nonresponsive to the views of the poor
might be of better quality by some measures. But it is difficult to deny that political inequalities exist; the
question is whether they are arranged to the benefit of the worst off. If they
are not arranged for the benefit of
the worst off, then it is possible that changing the values of n and x, i.e., giving more formal influence to the poorest, would serve as
appropriate compensation for their economic inequality.
The thing about a system where n > 1 and x > 0 is
that the value of any one person’s vote changes
as society becomes more or less equal. Regardless of how many classes we choose,
and what value we give to x, the more
income-equal the society, the more equal the value of the vote of rich and poor,
and in a perfectly income-equal society everyone would have exactly one vote.
By the same token, the higher the level of inequality, the higher the value of
the votes of the poor relative to the votes of the rich, and as inequality
increases, the more political power the poor
gain. x thus represents a kind of
“sensitivity parameter”: the higher its value, the more sensitive the political system will be to inequality.
Moreover, a system like this would bypass debates about which economic policies actually reduce
inequality or produce the most benefits for the worst off, i.e., which policies
would meet the “difference principle” (assuming, of course, that the difference
principle is the right principle of justice for socioeconomic matters; and it
may not be). It makes no assumptions about which kinds of economic policy
actually do help the poor; if laissez faire improves their position,
then the poor would be in the best position to approve of it; and if some other
policy worsens their relative
position, then the poor would get a right of “first refusal.” (As inequality
increases in a society, the poorest would gain more and more formal political
power). In the spirit of the difference principle, the rich are thus allowed to
benefit from (economic) inequality so long as the poor approve (with x and n setting the “approval parameters” of the system). Thus, the
higher the level of inequality, the more disenfranchised the rich become, and
the greater the compensation to the poor in the form of political inequality (benefiting the worst off the most), which in
turn might enable them to change those
policies. Of course, if your political theory does not depend on Rawlsian assumptions, this point might leave you cold;
but even utilitarians might see potential benefits here. (And your choice of x and n might say something about how much a person is willing to give up for the sake of economic equality).
Now, there are many potential problems here. The rich might underreport
their income. (Though this should only be a serious problem if n is large). The poor might choose policies
that are not in the interest of society as a whole. (But so can the rich; the
question is whether, on average, granting more political power to the poor
would result in more just decisions). They might redistribute property. (Which
would result in their losing
political power as economic inequality decreases).
If we start tweaking n and x who knows where we might end up. (We
could end up with political systems that grant more political power to the rich). Loss of formal political
influence by the rich might have unanticipated consequences in the form of additional
corruption and so on. Formal distinctions in voting power are an affront to the
equality of citizens, and offend our sense of fairness. (True, though people
take very large inequalities in elections to the US senate, for example,
completely in stride. Also see next point). Perhaps the most important objection
to a proposal like this, which Jay Ulfelder raised in conversation on G+ when I
posted the original idea, is that politics is not only about economic issues;
it is also about many other issues,
which we evaluate from the point of view of equal citizenship. Issues about
religion, civil liberties, etc. should not be subject to the predominant
influence of one social group; they concern all as equal citizens.
I grant that this is a powerful objection to a scheme like this.
But here’s a refinement that bypasses or at least mitigates it. Imagine a bicameral legislature. The
lower chamber is selected through an electoral system like the one described
above, where x = 1, and n = 10, for example. We could call this the
“Chamber of the Difference Principle.” The upper chamber, by contrast, is selected
through an electoral system of universal equal suffrage (x = 0, n = 1), perhaps including
some of the “random constituency” ideas I discussed in an earlier post to
ensure the representation of suitably general interests. We could call this the
“Chamber of Equal Citizenship.” Determining the exact relationship between
these two chambers is beyond the scope of this post; but the (Rawlsian) idea
would be that these two chambers would represent the two standpoints from which
we evaluate social institutions, and work together to produce law and policy.
Now, I myself don’t know for sure whether to take this idea seriously.
I lean toward thinking that a system like this is not only too shocking to our normal
ideas of fair representation to be ever politically possible, but is likely to
have some bad unanticipated public choice consequences. So I don’t know where I
would set x and n, if not at 0 and 1, even if I’ve half convinced myself that
higher values for both would be somewhat desirable. But I would like to know
where others would place these
values. Do you think that voting power should be inversely proportional to
income? If you’ve read this far, it would be great if you could answer this
poll.
[1]
Rawls does say in
section 36 of ToJ that the
political constitution of the just society would honor “the precept of one
elector one vote” as far as possible; but he could be wrong about that, even by his own lights; and anyway a Rawlsian
could argue that departures from the one elector, one vote precept are
justified in nonideal situations (as Rawls himself does). Furthermore, Rawls
does express concern about maintaining
the “fair value” of political liberty under conditions of economic
inequality, a problem which this system would potentially eliminate.
[2] This
is mathematically equivalent to a system in which the members of the richest
income class each have one vote, and members of the poorest class each have anx votes; it
doesn’t matter which description we use, except that in the second x should perhaps be called an
“empowerment” parameter (for the poor) rather than a disenfranchisement
parameter (for the rich).
Wednesday, August 22, 2012
Legitimacy as the Solow Residual of Political Science
Jay
Ulfelder kindly points his readers to my (recently updated!) working paper
on “The Irrelevance
of Legitimacy” in a
recent post where he expresses doubt about the explanatory usefulness of
the concept of legitimacy. As long-term readers will know, I am entirely in
agreement with Jay when he says that
We appeal to legitimacy when we
need to explain the persistence of political arrangements that defy our
materialist predictions, and when those arrangements do finally collapse, we
say that their failure has revealed a preceding loss of legitimacy. In statistical
terms, legitimacy is the label we attach to the residual, the portion of the
variance our mental models cannot explain. It is a tautology masquerading as a
causal force.
It occurs to me that “legitimacy” plays more or less the
same role in political science that “technology” sometimes plays in economics. Both are
residual concepts that provide an illusion of understanding but do not actually
explain much. In economics, talk of “technology” often obscures the fact that
we don’t have a very good general
theory of what explains economic growth, as Matt
Yglesias noted a couple of weeks ago:
Economists have shown that modern
economic growth can't be accounted for merely by growth in the size of the
labor force or by accumulation of additional capital. You need to add a third
element into the mix. This element is sometimes called "total factor
productivity" and sometimes called "technology," but it
represents a statistical discrepency, not an inquiry into independently
identifiable properties of technological growth. It's like Molière's doctors
explaining that opium puts people to sleep because of its virtus dormitiva.
If the discrepency were small,
this might not be a big deal and we'd say that economists had shown that
capital accumulation is the key to economic growth. But it's not small. What's
been found is that economic growth is largely unexplained. Using the word
"technology" as a label for the discrepency makes it sound as if the
issue is much better understood than it really is.
Technology is here the “Solow residual:” all the
different mechanisms by which economic growth occurs that are not accounted for by simple measures of
labor and capital utilization. But there are many such mechanisms! Education,
changes in political institutions and property rights, the invention of new
machines and business methods, new forms of economic organization, changes
in social roles, norms, and culture, etc. all can contribute to economic
growth beyond increases in labor supply and capital accumulation; but only some
of these mechanisms correspond to what we normally think about when we say “technology,”
and forgetting this is likely to lead to incorrect inferences. Moreover, we do not actually know which of these
mechanisms is the most important in general, and hence which government policies would be most likely
to increase growth.
Similarly, “legitimacy” is the label we typically use in
political science for all the factors that sustain social order or norms beyond
obvious coercion and material incentives. We all agree that the persistence of
norms and social order cannot be fully (or
even mostly) explained by crude
material incentives and obvious coercion; but by subsuming all these “other”
factors under a single label we miss the fact that they are really quite
various. Collective action problems, rational conservatism, signalling
conventions, emotional attachments, habits of discourse and conceptual blinders, identity and
affiliation entanglements, sophistry and propaganda, even sincere beliefs in
the rightness of the norms or forms of social order in question (for a detailed examination of these mechanisms, read my paper); all of these mechanisms
can contribute to their maintenance, and only some of them are close to the folk model of “legitimacy,” in which norms persist because in some sense those subject to them "like" them or at least "accept" them on their own terms. (A model that I take to be false in most relevant cases). Moreover, to the extent that we are interested in changing particular social
norms or forms of social order, we will do better to think in terms of how particular mechanisms sustain these
norms, rather than in terms of “legitimacy.”
Friday, August 17, 2012
More Rawlsian Thought Experiments: An Inverse Income Voting System
(For some unknown reason, re-reading Rawls stimulates my weird
idea generator. Another politically impossible proposal here, presented as a
thought experiment)
Thinking about the difference principle today, it occurred
to me that most of the discussion on the topic tends to be overly focused on
the economic institutions that would
ensure that the least advantaged group in society would fare best. Yet the
difference principle is not restricted in its application to economic inequalities;
in fact, the principle specifies that inequalities of authority and political
power must also be justified to the
worst off group in society: “[t]he second principle applies, in the first
approximation, to the distribution of income and wealth and to the design of institutions
that make use of differences in authority and responsibility” (§11,
p. 53, emphasis mine). Is a standard democratic system – with
its panoply of elections, constitutional protections, and so on –justified in those
terms? Rawls seems to assume so, even though standard democratic institutions entail
clear inequalities in authority and responsibility which are not obviously to
the maximum benefit of the worst off.
Moreover, to the extent that Rawls discusses the connection
between political and economic inequalities, he tends to think of the direction
of causation as going from economics to politics. Unjustifiable political inequalities
in authority and responsibility (as, for example, when the rich have undue
influence in the political process) would be remedied, in his view, once objectionable
economic inequalities are taken care of, which seems reasonable enough; after
all, he notes, such inequalities are correlated with one another (§16,
p. 83). With low levels of economic inequality, widely dispersed ownership
of the means of production, and a healthy dose of public campaign finance,
Rawls argues, whatever differences in authority and responsibility political
institutions would still produce would be justifiable to the least advantaged (cf.
§13, p. 71, §36,
p. 198).
But why wait until such inequalities are fully remedied? Imagine
that instead of the standard, one person, one vote system, we had a voting
system where the poorest person with any income got 1 vote, the person with
twice the income of the poorest person got ½ a vote, and a person with 20,000
times the income of the poorest person got 1/20,000th of a vote. “Income”
here includes any government transfers; people with no income would have 1
vote, just as the poorest people with any income. The specific value of the
vote would be linked to the income records on file with the national tax agency,
and no one could vote who was not linked in some way to the tax system. We
might use broad categories instead of specific incomes – say, people making
less than $10,000 a year get one vote, people making up to $20,000 half a vote,
and so on; and of course we might decide that a different weighting of votes is
required. [Update: it occurs to me that using the median income would be easier to set up. For example, voters below the median income each get one vote, voters between the median and twice the median get half, and so on.] Whatever the case, poorer people would have more formal influence
than richer people.
In a fully income-equal society, everyone would have 1 vote; in an
extremely unequal society, the very poorest would have the most political influence.
High-flying hedge fund managers with extremely high incomes likely would have an
infinitesimal vote, though they would of course still have many means of
exercising influence. After all, elections cost money, and the rich are more
able to run for election and lobby legislators. But the idea is that the least
advantaged groups would have compensating advantages, as politicians would have
to cater to the greatest mass of votes; yet these advantages would diminish as transfer payments
increased, or society became more equal. Note also that the specific value of a
person’s vote would fluctuate throughout their lifetime, being very high when the
person is very young or very old, and very low during their peak earning years.
(The system might work kind of like an automatic means test for politically
distributed benefits, baked right into the political structure).
Would there be anything wrong with this system, from a
Rawlsian point of view? Everyone can still vote and run for office, so the
first principle of Rawls’ theory - the principle guaranteeing the equal basic liberties - is not overtly violated; and it seems to me that
the inequalities of authority and responsibility produced by this system are
more clearly justifiable to the worst off group in society than the
inequalities produced by a standard democratic system. For one thing, it provides
the least advantaged in society with the fair
value of their political liberties in a direct, unmediated way that complicated systems of campaign finance cannot match. Moreover, a
political system along these lines bypasses the theoretical discussion about which economic system would best
produce outcomes in conformity with the difference principle; different proposals
can be tried, and if they worsened the lot of the least advantaged, the poor would
gradually acquire sufficient political
clout to overturn them. (In theory, this is compatible with pure libertarian laissez faire, so long as such laissez faire actually does improve the
condition of the least advantaged group).
Like any oddball proposal, this is very likely a bad idea.
(I can imagine all kinds of bad incentives to underreport income, for example, and I’m
not sure it would fit with the well-entrenched idea that having an equal voice
is a mark of respect of equal citizenship.) But I’m curious: are there specifically Rawlsian
grounds to reject this sort of
system? (I'm sure there are other grounds). And what are the obvious problems I’ve missed in here? Does this lead
to a sustainable politico-economic equilibrium, or simply to an intensification
of class conflict?
[Update 2, 20 August 2012: fixed some minor typos. Also thought of some further refinements. Suppose we divide the income distribution into N equal quantiles. The voters in the lowest class have one vote, and the voters in the highest class have (1/(N^x)) fractional vote, where x is a parameter determining how extreme the disenfranchisement of the rich is. When x=0 everyone has one vote, as today; when x=1, the disenfranchisement is strictly proportional to class position, so the each person in the nth quantile has 1/n votes; but we could set x between 0 and 1, leading to a range of different weightings of formal influence for the poorest depending both on the number of "classes" and on the extent of disenfranchisement with income. With few classes and low x, the system is close to our own; with many classes and large x, there is a very steep disenfranchisement curve. What values of these parameters would be chosen behind the veil of ignorance?]
[Update 2, 20 August 2012: fixed some minor typos. Also thought of some further refinements. Suppose we divide the income distribution into N equal quantiles. The voters in the lowest class have one vote, and the voters in the highest class have (1/(N^x)) fractional vote, where x is a parameter determining how extreme the disenfranchisement of the rich is. When x=0 everyone has one vote, as today; when x=1, the disenfranchisement is strictly proportional to class position, so the each person in the nth quantile has 1/n votes; but we could set x between 0 and 1, leading to a range of different weightings of formal influence for the poorest depending both on the number of "classes" and on the extent of disenfranchisement with income. With few classes and low x, the system is close to our own; with many classes and large x, there is a very steep disenfranchisement curve. What values of these parameters would be chosen behind the veil of ignorance?]
Monday, August 13, 2012
Musical Chairs, Veto Constituencies, Accountability Juries, and other Random Ideas: Further Thoughts on Randomizing Electoral Constituencies
(Attention conservation notice: some more thoughts on this
proposal, which gained a modest amount of internet attention in the last
couple of days – see Dylan Matthews here,
Matt Yglesias here,
and Evan Soltas here).
Anyway, I’m sure there are huge problems with all of these proposals, which I don’t expect to be political reality any time soon; this is more a thought experiment than anything else. I would nevertheless be interested to hear what some of these problems are, or what alternatives people can come up with.
Having slept on it and seen a few responses, I am not yet
convinced that the proposal I sketched in the post below would actually be a bad idea (though it probably is!). The basic idea
is that the electoral constituency or electorate –
the group of people who “selects” the legislator – should be separated from the accountability constituency or electorate – the
group of people who “disciplines” the legislator1
– in such a way that neither the legislator nor the electors would know in
advance who the latter group would be. Such a system would (in theory) mimic some
of the structural features of a Rawlsian “veil of ignorance,” so that
legislators could not tailor their appeal to any particular group of people but
are instead incentivized to speak and act in ways that can be publicly
justified to any group in society. But there are a variety of ways of
accomplishing this, as I hinted at in the original post. Some of these are very
close to current practice; others are not so close. I want to consider here in
detail a few of these variations:
- “Musical chairs” representation. This is the
simplest form of the proposal. (My original idea was in fact closer to option 2
below, “random veto constituencies,” though it seems to have been quickly
simplified into this form, which is at any rate simpler and more elegant). Under
musical chairs representation, non-incumbent candidates can run in any
constituency they choose, but incumbent candidates running for re-election are randomly
assigned a constituency shortly before the election date (say, a month or so
earlier). The random constituency can be their original electoral constituency
(let’s call this the “initial” constituency). We do not need to imagine that
the incumbent draws any constituency with equal probability; a system where the
incumbent has a higher probability of drawing his/her initial constituency
could strengthen the incentive to do the kinds of constituent service that a
lot of people seem to find valuable.
More formally, let’s say there are N constituencies or districts in the system; come election time, incumbents can draw their own initial constituency with probability p, where p > 1/N, and any other constituency with probability (1-p)/(N-1). (More complicated assignments of weights are of course possible). When p = 1, the system works identically to current practice – the incumbent always draws his own constituency; when p = 1/N, the incumbent can draw any constituency with equal probability. We might thus think of p as a measure of “localism” in the system. The lower p, the more the re-election seeking politician will need to act in ways that can be publicly justified to any constituency in the country, but he will of course have less incentive to do constituency service or to represent his locality. p can also serve as a measure of incumbent advantage; the higher p, the higher the advantage, all other things equal.
What might be the benefits of a system where p < 1? By facing the possibility of having to compete for re-election in a constituency other than the one where he has been originally elected, a politician would of course need to avoid acting in ways that can incur disapproval beyond his constituency. But he would still have incentives to represent his constituency, pace Dylan Matthews. For one thing, the chance of drawing his initial constituency is nonzero, and a reputation for serving the constituency one is representing would still be a valuable asset in a race in a different district. Indeed, they might still be able to too easily promise to extract rents on behalf of local interests, as Evan Soltas notes, though I imagine it would be harder to promise this credibly when they don’t know which district they would be representing in the next election. At any rate, promises of local rents aren’t the only criterion by which electorates judge the suitability of candidates, and this system would weaken the appeal of these promises. Moreover, while a district or electorate could insist on electing candidates with purely local appeal, these would, I suspect, tend to be one-term wonders, as would “extreme” candidates. Assuming the distribution of voter preferences is not itself polarized for other reasons, the system would tend to moderate polarization over time as candidates strategically target the “modal” constituency to a greater or lesser extent, depending on the strength of their convictions and their level of risk aversion.
Elections might nevertheless become more competitive under this system, since p < 1 implies a lower level of incumbent advantage, which might be a good thing (more competitive elections tend to be associated with more public goods provision, though this varies depending on the kind of competition). More importantly, as Matt Yglesias notes, the forms of public justification themselves would shift. An incumbent US congressman who defended agricultural subsidies in Iowa during his term, for example, would need to do so in terms that would resist potential sceptical examination by an electorate in New York. And one should not discount the satisfaction electors would get from giving a sound thumping to a politician they find particularly obnoxious but would not, under current practices, normally be able to defeat. (Soltas’ objection that it “weakens accountability structures to have your performance judged by someone else than whoever installed you” is I think overstated; electors judging the performance of a non-local candidate can always opt for the local challenger, or judge the non-local candidate on the basis of his/her record on issues or national significance, as they often seem to do anyway, and as is perhaps appropriate for candidates to a national legislature). Nevertheless, it is probably safe to say that in the aggregate this system would not produce large shifts in policy from the status quo; after all, many mixed-member proportional systems (New Zealand!) try to achieve similar balances of “national” and “local” concerns, even if they use somewhat different mechanisms and have somewhat different effects on the forms of public justification. - Random veto constituencies. My original proposal tried to preserve local representation in a slightly different way. Perhaps
the simplest form of it is the following: non-incumbent candidates are elected
according to the vote totals in the constituency they are running, but
incumbent candidates are subject to a veto
in a randomly selected constituency (assigned shortly before the election). In
essence, the challenger must win only in
the local constituency, but the incumbent must win in both the local and the randomly selected constituency. If the
incumbent loses in the randomly assigned constituency but wins in the local
constituency, the challenger takes
power; hence the idea of a veto. The
system could make allowance for extremely popular incumbents, so that getting,
say, 60% of the vote in their local constituency means that they only have to get
40% of the vote in their randomly-assigned constituency, and getting 80% of the
vote in the local constituency means they only have to get 20% of the vote in
the randomly assigned constituency. (Again, the chances of drawing a particular
constituency could be suitably weighted to favour nearby constituencies, for
example).
It seems to me that this system would have most of the advantages of the previous one while preserving the possibility of strongly-rooted local representation. Races remain local, but politicians cannot act in ways that have a strong probability of being disapproved of elsewhere in the country; and incumbent advantage is strongly diminished. Nevertheless, it seems possible that a system of vetoes could create a lot of ill-will; I’m sure people in say, rural South Carolina, would not relish having their choices of representatives vetoed by people in San Francisco or vice-versa. So it does not seem politically sustainable in the long run, even if it would enable the schadenfreude of spectators to see politicians having to justify themselves to hostile electorates beyond their home turf (a benefit that is not to be underestimated; see Jeffrey Edward Green’s The Eyes of the People for a full academic defence). - Accountability juries. One problem with the proposals above is that they favour geographical units of representation at the expense of other possibilities. While randomization of such geographical units may have some benefits, certain interests are never going to be well represented on that basis. One could, however, modify the idea of veto constituencies so that the veto would be exercised by juries selected on the basis of some non-geographical criterion. For example, imagine that before each election, we drew five juries of 500 people each selected on the basis of income – the first jury being composed of 500 people randomly selected from the first income quintile, the second from the second, and so on. Each incumbent candidate is then randomly assigned, shortly before the election, to make his/her case before one of these juries; you could be assigned to speak before a jury of the poor, or before a jury of the rich, but you would not know which one in advance. We could have weeklong, televised trials, perhaps presided over by special investigating magistrates, in an echo of the “audits” Ancient Athens subjected its officials to at the end of their terms. The jury could then vote (perhaps with some suitable supermajority requirement) on whether or not the incumbent should be allowed to run for re-election (in that election; no permanent disqualification is envisioned). The possibilities here are, of course, much more various: how we would organize such juries, run the trials, and so on would be crucial questions. I suspect a system like this would shift policy more radically, but I like the idea of having representatives having to justify themselves to randomly selected constituencies that do not have a geographical basis.
Anyway, I’m sure there are huge problems with all of these proposals, which I don’t expect to be political reality any time soon; this is more a thought experiment than anything else. I would nevertheless be interested to hear what some of these problems are, or what alternatives people can come up with.
Friday, August 10, 2012
Rawlsian Legislatures: A Modest Proposal
(Attention conservation notice: various harebrained schemes
I cooked up preparing for a seminar on Rawls that appear to structurally mimic ideas
about a “veil of ignorance.” Of purely theoretical interest.)
[Update 13 August: see also my further thoughts on these proposals here].
[Update 13 August: see also my further thoughts on these proposals here].
John Rawls’ A
Theory of Justice famously introduced the idea of an “original position,”
a hypothetical situation in which citizens would come together behind a “veil
of ignorance” to select principles of justice that can regulate their common
life. There are different ways of understanding the OP, but one useful way –
which Rawls himself favoured later in life – is to imagine that the “contracting
parties” in the original position are not the members of society themselves,
but rather their representatives. Each of these representatives – modelled as rational
negotiators – is then supposed to bargain for the best possible “deal” acceptable
to the citizens they represent on the terms of cooperation in society, but without knowing which specific set of
citizens they represent. This is supposed to ensure that the negotiating
parties will only agree on principles that would be acceptable to all citizens
as “free and equal.” Leif Wenar in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy describes
the basic point well:
The original position is a
thought experiment: an imaginary situation in which each real citizen has a
representative, and all of these representatives come to an agreement on which
principles of justice should order the political institutions of the real
citizens. Were actual citizens to get together in real time to try to agree to
principles of justice for their society the bargaining among them would be
influenced by all sorts of factors irrelevant to justice, such as who could
appear most threatening or who could hold out longest. The original position
abstracts from all such irrelevant factors. In effect the original position is
a situation in which each citizen is represented as only a free and equal
citizen, as wanting only what free and equal citizens want, and as trying to
agree to principles for the basic structure while situated fairly with respect
to other citizens. For example citizens' basic equality is modeled in the
original position by imagining that the parties who represent real citizens are
symmetrically situated: no citizen's representative is able to threaten any
other citizen's representative, or to hold out longer for a better deal.
The most striking feature of the
original position is the veil of ignorance, which prevents other arbitrary
facts about citizens from influencing the agreement among their
representatives. As we have seen, Rawls holds that the fact that a citizen is
for example of a certain race, class, and gender is no reason for social
institutions to favor or disfavor him. Each party in the original position is
therefore deprived of knowledge of the race, class, and gender of the real
citizen they represent. In fact the veil of ignorance deprives the parties,
Rawls says, of all facts about citizens that are irrelevant to the choice of
principles of justice: not only their race, class, and gender but also their
age, natural endowments, and more. Moreover the veil of ignorance also screens
out specific information about the citizens' society so as to get a clearer
view of the permanent features of a just social system.
In Rawls’ view, the veil of ignorance can also play a role
in the selection and evaluation of constitutions and laws. While the
representatives of the citizens in the OP are supposed to select principles of
justice in complete ignorance of the citizens’ class, gender, plan of life, and
even the general features of their society, the veil can be “lifted” gradually
to allow the representatives to agree on how these principles apply to more concrete
institutions. This is what Rawls calls the “four-stage
sequence”:
After agreeing on the two
principles and a principle of just savings, the parties then proceed further
through the four-stage sequence, tailoring these general principles to the
particular conditions of the society of the citizens they represent. The veil
of ignorance that screens out information about society's general features is
gradually thinned, and the parties use the new information to decide on
progressively more determinate applications of the two principles.
At the second stage the parties
are given more information about the society's political culture and economic
development, and take on the task of crafting a constitution that realizes the
two principles. At the third stage the parties learn still more about the
details of the society, and agree to specific laws and policies that realize
the two principles within the constitutional framework decided at the second
stage. At the final stage the parties have full information about the society,
and reason as judges and administrators to apply the previously-agreed laws and
policies to particular cases. When the four stages are complete the principles
of justice as fairness are fully articulated for the society's political life.
Re-reading Rawls recently while preparing to teach a class, it struck me that it would be
possible to mimic some of the structural features of this interpretation of the
veil of ignorance in actual legislatures.
The simplest way to do this, it seems to me, would be to
divorce electoral constituencies from
accountability constituencies. Suppose
legislators are elected in a relatively large number of small single-member constituencies
(I’m thinking of a small place like New Zealand, where electorates are small,
but one could imagine more complex schemes elsewhere). They go to a Parliament or
Congress and negotiate laws as best as they can. At the end of their term,
however, they must justify themselves to a randomly
allocated constituency (not necessarily the one in which they were elected),
which decides whether or not they can run for re-election. (A variant: the
accountability constituency [also?] has the power to impose a financial penalty
on the legislator if it finds the justifications for its actions lacking). The
trick here is that the constituency that can hold the legislator accountable is
not known in advance, either to the
electors or to the elected MPs. If Rawls is correct, this should encourage
elected legislators to negotiate “fair” legislative proposals –legislative proposals
that are broadly acceptable to all in society.
An example may help. Imagine the electors for Wellington
Central elect Grant Robertson
their MP. At the end of his term, the Electoral Commission randomly assigns him
a different constituency. Say he draws Auckland central, for example. Robertson then has to go to Auckland
Central to defend his record in parliament; let’s say he’s given one month to
make his case. Auckland Central then holds an “up or down” vote deciding
whether or not he can run in the next election. If he’s voted down, he cannot
run in that electoral period (though he may run in later periods – no permanent
disqualification is envisioned here); otherwise, he gets to run again, if he so
wishes, in Wellington Central.
One can easily imagine all kinds of problems with this
system. (Consider the possibilities for strategic voting; and I’m sure the pros
could come up with all kinds of ways of gaming this system). But I’m having way
too much fun thinking about it to worry about these inconveniences right now. For example,
imagine accountability constituencies that are functional or income-based rather
than geographical. Legislators could be elected in standard geographical
constituencies, but then randomly assigned to income-defined constituencies to
make their case for being allowed to run for re-election. We might imagine that
large “juries” of people from specific income quantiles could be empanelled,
and MPs randomly assigned, at the end of their terms, to make the case for
their policies to one of these juries in week-long trials. The juries then
decide whether or not the MP is to be allowed to run again. Or imagine we got
rid entirely of electoral constituencies. Instead, people would vote on the abstract
composition of the legislature (expressing their preferences not only about the
party composition of the legislature, as in closed list PR systems, but perhaps
also their preferences about the level of education or income legislators must
have, what percentage of legislators must be women, of a particular race, etc.).
Political parties are then tasked to fill a legislature with these
characteristics, but the legislators must then, at the end of their term, justify
themselves to a randomly assigned constituency, which has the power to impose
fines (and perhaps to award prizes).
Ok, so what’s the benefit of this, you may ask? If Rawls is
correct, the fact that legislators would not know in advance to whom in society they would be held
accountable would mean that they would be inclined to act in ways that are “publically
justifiable” to all, including the “least advantaged.” What do people think?
Monday, August 06, 2012
Mixed Constitutions vs. Mixed Economies (or, Ancient and Modern Liberalisms)
(Attention conservation notice: Inspired by a student’s
comment a while back, this has languished in my drafts folder. Contains speculative intellectual history, implausible connections between ancient and modern concepts, and self-promotion; nevertheless, I thought it would be worth trying out the argument)
The ancient Greco-Roman idea of the “mixed constitution” is
usually taken to be the ancestor of modern (post 18th-century) constitutional
ideas about “checks and balances” and the “division of powers.” This is fine as
far as it goes; the early modern writers who first proposed and defended these latter
ideas in a systematic way – people like Harrington, Locke, and Montesquieu, for example – seem to have been
influenced to some degree by Greek and Roman theories of the mixed
constitution. They used these ideas as one of the lenses through which they
interpreted British constitutional practice of the 17th and 18th
centuries; and there is certainly a sort of family resemblance between the
ancient idea about the need for “mixture” in a constitution and the modern idea
that a constitution should implement some checks on state power through the
functional division of authority among different “branches” of the government.
However, as many people have noted, ancient ideas about the
mixed constitution are in many ways quite different from modern ideas about the
need for a functional division of authority to prevent abuses of state power. Even
the guiding metaphors are different: “mixture” and “separation” denote contrary
ideas. But perhaps more importantly, it strikes me that ideas about the mixed
constitution played a role in ancient Greco-Roman political discourse that is
very different from the role that ideas about “checks and balances” came to
play in modern political discourse, and that is in fact surprisingly similar to
the role ideas about the “mixed economy” – an economy that incorporates both
market mechanisms and government intervention – play in contemporary political
thought. I don’t mean this as a claim about intellectual history:
ideas about the “mixed economy” today clearly owe nothing to ancient ideas
about the mixed constitution. I mean it as a claim about the conceptual place
of ideas within particular discourses or debates. Let me try to explain.
As I argue in much pedantic detail in a piece I published
last year somewhat misleadingly entitled “Cicero and the Stability of States” (History
of Political Thought 32(3): 397-423 [gated,
ungated] –
the first half is a survey of ideas about the mixed constitution in Plato,
Aristotle, and Polybius), ancient ideas about the mixed constitution have two
strands.
On the one hand, there is a concern with domination by powerful
people and groups. Here the idea of the mixed constitution serves as a model of
the “constraints” that should be imposed on the powerful to prevent tyranny,
and in this sense it plays a very similar role to ideas of “checks and
balances.” However, whereas modern discussions about the separation of powers tend
to emphasize the need for a functional division
of the tasks of government (into legislative,
executive, and judicial activities, for example) to prevent abuses of state power, ancient discussions of the mixed
constitution tend instead to emphasize a social division
of power among significant social groups to prevent its monopolization (a group “becoming”
the state, so to speak). The “simple” or “unmixed” regimes are precisely those
regimes where one social group – the rich, the poor, military leaders –
monopolizes power (for good or ill; the unmixed regimes are not always
considered bad, but they are always considered fragile for a variety of reasons);
by contrast, the “mixed” regimes are precisely those where power is “shared,”
or, metaphorically, these are the regimes which "mix" the monopolistic regimes so that no social group has uncontested dominance over the others.
To put the point very roughly, I suspect the modern emphasis
on separating power goes hand in hand
with an emerging consciousness of “the state” as a distinct unified
institutional actor that can develop interests that are independent of those of
other significant social groups (including dominant groups), and hence is
concerned with the institutional mechanisms that can limit its ability to act in dominating ways; ancient political thought,
by contrast, has no such consciousness of a “state” as distinct from the social
groups that exercise political power (most Ancient Greco-Roman societies had
nothing like a state in the Weberian sense of the word anyway), and hence is more
concerned with the compromises that various groups need to make to share power stably
in ways that are beneficial to all. This is only an imprecise sketch of a
complex history, of course. After all, early modern liberal political thought
was often also concerned with the problems
posed by the domination of one social group over another; 19th
century debates about suffrage are full of fears about what would happen if the
poor were allowed to directly elect representatives and hence dominate the
state, for example. And 17th and 18th century notions of
“estate representation” do fit in quite naturally with ancient ideas about
mixed constitutions. Yet I am tempted to
speculate in a vaguely Marxist way that ancient Greco-Roman political thought
was more attuned to the permanent class conflicts of agrarian societies than
early modern liberal thought, perhaps because the latter in part grew out of reflections
on the management of confessional or sectarian conflicts in which the state was
never merely a class agent, unlike the former.
At any rate, this concern with “sharing” power among significant
social groups leads to a second strand of thought about political “mixture.”
Here the idea of the mixed constitution serves as a model of the compromises
that are possible and necessary between groups whose conceptions of justice –
their conceptions of the appropriate distribution of the “benefits and burdens”
in the community, their ideas about the appropriate level of hierarchy and
equality in the organization of society, and so on – differ systematically
according to their positions in society. For example, both Plato and Aristotle
(and to a lesser degree other extant writers) suggest that the poor and the rich
develop conceptions of justice that have a certain “bias” towards their own
structural position: while the poor or the people tend to develop a conception
of justice that emphasizes their equality
as citizens, and hence the need for an equal distribution of power and
authority in the community (expressed most radically in the lotteries of
Athens), the rich or the elite tend to develop a conception of justice that
emphasizes their inequality – their
distinctiveness – and hence the need for an unequal
distribution of power and authority (expressed in the demand for closed
oligarchies and in justifications that claim the right to rule for those who
contribute the most to the community, or those who are wisest, or have the most
military virtue). Conflict between major social groups is not simply a clash of
naked self-interest (at least not always), but rather appears as a contest
between rival moralized conceptions of hierarchy, equality, and fair
distribution.
For these Greek (and later Roman) writers, the key
theoretical problem thus turns out to be how to bridge these divergent
conceptions of justice for the sake of political stability while also promoting
as far as possible various other important goods – freedom, independence, the
effectiveness of the community as a fighting force, social solidarity, prudent
decisionmaking, etc. How can political power be shared so that these
contrasting conceptions of justice can all find some place in the community without monopolizing the whole, while maintaining a viable, even flourishing society in other respects?
This problem is complicated both by material factors (extreme inequality makes it difficult to bridge the conceptions of justice of significant social groups, in the view of most of the extant Greek writers who talk about this problem) and by the fact that
these group-relative conceptions of justice, however faulty, cannot be fully “educated
away.” That is, whatever the truth of the matter about justice is (and Greek
and Roman thinkers thought this was an answerable
question) it is simply not possible to consistently convince people in structurally different positions that their
conceptions of justice are incorrect. (At best, education can soften the edges
of those differing conceptions of justice, but not transform them consistently).
The “mixed constitution” is then an attempt to describe how one might give all these different
conceptions of justice – or different ideas about what is valuable, or what
gives people title to rule – some place within the polity despite the fact that they are partially incorrect (because one-sided) and hence in some ways damaging to the community, and despite the fact that they cannot be "corrected," while not wholly sacrificing
other important values. In Plato, for example, the test of a well-organized
mixed constitution is that it balances the characteristic values associated
with “democracy” (where the poor or the many are dominant) and “monarchy” (a
synecdoche for all regimes where small elites are dominant) so as to promote philia (social solidarity), eleutheria (freedom and political
independence) and phronesis (prudent
decisionmaking). Let me quote myself:
The Athenian Stranger [the main speaker in
Plato’s Laws] suggests
that a constitution can achieve these three objectives by “mixing” in the right
proportion the values traditionally associated with monarchy, especially
Persia, and the values traditionally associated with democracy, especially
Athens (693d). “Monarchical” values emphasize subordination and status
hierarchies, and thus enhance the coordination of action necessary to effective
military power, i.e., the kind of power that ensures eleutheria as political independence (694a). But if they are
over-emphasized, they disrupt both the solidarity and affection (philia) between rulers and ruled and the ability of information and
insight to flow to the rulers (phronesis; 694a-b), increasing the city’s
vulnerability to external forces and diminishing the ability of rulers to
actually rule for the common good (697d-698a). By contrast, “democratic” values
emphasize personal autonomy and equality, and thus enhance the solidarity and
affection between rulers and ruled as well as the flow of information
throughout the city, which makes the city able to defend itself intelligently
at least so long as it can coordinate its actions through its laws and rulers
even against vastly superior forces (cf. 698b-699d). But if they are
over-emphasized, the city loses both its ability to recognize and defer to
actual expertise (and hence loses intelligence; cf. 701a) and the ability to
coordinate properly that submission to laws and rulers provide. It thus
disintegrates into “every man for himself” (cf. 699c-d), again making it vulnerable
to external forces.
Properly constructed institutions will ensure that
the citizens will be properly submissive to the laws and the rulers (indeed,
that they will “fear” and “revere” the laws and the rulers, cf. 698b), but will
also grant enough personal autonomy and ensure enough status equality to ensure
that phronesis flows through the city
and rulers and ruled share enough affection for each other. Such a constitution
will “weave together” the “mother constitutions” of monarchy and democracy (693d)
in the sense that it will induce a measured combination of their characteristic
values capable of simultaneously ensuring solidarity and affection between
rulers and ruled, intelligence in the actions of the city, and the preservation
of its political independence. (moi,
pp. 403-404)
Though “liberalism” as such did not exist in the Ancient
Greco-Roman world, the idea of the mixed constitution thus seems to me to be designed
to deal with problems similar to those that have motivated much modern liberal
thought: how to deal with intractable conflicts of value (about justice, in
this case) when no significant social group can be assumed to have a monopoly
on the truth (the philosopher does not count as a social group, even if she does have the truth about justice) in a relatively
peaceful way. But ancient mixed constitution thinking (at least the mostly
Greek variant of it before Cicero that has come down to us), unlike classical
liberalism, tended to see these problems in the context of deep-seated,
ineradicable distributional conflicts; and as such, it seems to me, it played a
role in political thought similar to the role the idea of a “mixed economy”
plays today.
Modern economic debates about the role of the state in the economy
are obviously never merely technical debates; they usually invoke, either
implicitly or explicitly, different conceptions of justice and fairness, and
different answers to the question about the kinds of power that partisans of
these conceptions of justice and fairness ought to have in society. (Consider: "taxation is theft" vs. "you didn't build that"). They are
debates about what is the right distribution of burdens and benefits in society,
and draw on deep-seated intuitions about desert, property, and the like that appear
to vary among distinct social groups. The idea of a mixed economy then serves
as a model – varying in detail depending on its particular proponent, of course – of the appropriate
distribution of social power among partisans of different conceptions of
distributive justice, including both a description of the kinds of constraints that should be imposed on powerful social groups (e.g., how democratic states should constrain markets and vice-versa) and a description of the kinds of
compromises that partisans of particular ideas of fairness or justice must make
while still promoting efficiency (the modern equivalent of the Platonic “prudent
decisionmaking” or phronesis), common
identity (the modern equivalent of the Platonic philia), and personal autonomy (the modern equivalent of eleutheria).
Proponents of a mixed economy of course disagree
about the specific institutions of that would instantiate it properly, just as
Plato, Aristotle, Polybius, and Cicero had different views about proper mixture
in a constitution. My point is more about how the abstract model of the mixed
economy seems to serve as a reference point for attempting to find pragmatic
compromises among social groups with ineradicably different views concerning distributive justice and enduring, if unbalanced, forms of social power (numbers vs. economic power, for example) even if we think that some of these views are correct (or more correct than others). We might say that like the mixed constitution in antiquity, the mixed economy today serves as a
standard description of the second best.
Update 7 August: fixed some oddities of grammar and missing words.
Update 7 August: fixed some oddities of grammar and missing words.
Tuesday, July 10, 2012
New Book: A Stranger's Knowledge: Statesmanship, Philosophy, and Law in Plato's Statesman
Due to a vaguely superstitious reluctance to make an announcement until I had the final physical copies in my hands, I neglected to announce here the recent publication of my first book, A Stranger's Knowledge: Statesmanship, Philosophy, and Law in Plato's Statesman (Parmenides, Amazon). But I now have physical proof that the book is truly available!
(And it's reasonably priced, too, for an academic monograph).
My interest in Plato's Statesman may seem odd to regular readers of this blog, given that it has morphed into a blog on dictatorships, cults of personality, democratization, and the like. But this blog first started (years ago) as a home for orphaned footnotes that were excised from the book's first draft (click on the archives around 2007 to find some of them; it has taken me a long time to get here). Plato also remains the most prominent, interesting, and challenging defender of the rule of knowledge against the rule of the people, so my turn to the study of nondemocracy is perhaps not so surprising; and the many years I spent working on my interpretation of this puzzling dialogue have continued to nourish my thoughts in unexpected ways (e.g., my series on epistemic arguments for conservatism).
The dialogue, at any rate, is an exquisite puzzle, which is probably what attracted me to it in graduate school in the first place. A conversation between an unnamed "stranger" from Elea and a young and pliable mathematician named Socrates (not the Socrates of most of the dialogues, who witnesses the conversation but, aside from a short prologue, never says a word), the dialogue purports to be part of a trio of conversations set right before the famous trial of Socrates, each of them concerned with defining a different figure: the sophist, the statesman, and the philosopher. But though the Sophist exists, the Philosopher dialogue does not exist (and it is likely that it was never intended to exist); instead, the Sophist is placed in fictional continuity with the Theaetetus, Plato's most important dialogue on knowledge. The conversation itself is delightfully weird. It is full of strange distinctions and odd conclusions (including an elaborate joke about human beings being "featherless bipeds" or "two-legged pigs," which was apparently fodder for ancient pranksters like Diogenes the Cynic), dead ends and mistakes that are extensively discussed and acknowledged within the conversation itself, a long and detailed digression on the art of weaving, and a complex myth about a great "cosmic reversal" of motion in which human beings are depicted as being born from the earth in old age and living their lives in reverse. All of this leads to an ambiguous defense of the rule of law as "second best" and a characterization of the genuine statesman as someone whose main concern is the timing of existential decisions for the polity as a whole, in apparent tension with Plato's classic discussion of the "philosopher king" in the Republic.
The puzzle lies in trying to make sense of how all of these disparate elements (which draw explicit attention both to their ill-fittingness and their fittingness) fit together as a single pedagogical and theoretical exercise; and the book is my attempt to provide a solution to this puzzle that makes sense of the dialogue not merely as a methodological discussion (as most scholars argue) but as a work of political philosophy that is decisively concerned with the question of what "political knowledge" could even mean. I may say more about my answer to this question later (though, as with most Platonic dialogues, most of the fun lies in trying to understand the movement of the conversation rather than in the answers to which the conversation arrives); buy the book (or tell your friendly academic librarian to buy the book) to find out the full version.
(And it's reasonably priced, too, for an academic monograph).
My interest in Plato's Statesman may seem odd to regular readers of this blog, given that it has morphed into a blog on dictatorships, cults of personality, democratization, and the like. But this blog first started (years ago) as a home for orphaned footnotes that were excised from the book's first draft (click on the archives around 2007 to find some of them; it has taken me a long time to get here). Plato also remains the most prominent, interesting, and challenging defender of the rule of knowledge against the rule of the people, so my turn to the study of nondemocracy is perhaps not so surprising; and the many years I spent working on my interpretation of this puzzling dialogue have continued to nourish my thoughts in unexpected ways (e.g., my series on epistemic arguments for conservatism).
The dialogue, at any rate, is an exquisite puzzle, which is probably what attracted me to it in graduate school in the first place. A conversation between an unnamed "stranger" from Elea and a young and pliable mathematician named Socrates (not the Socrates of most of the dialogues, who witnesses the conversation but, aside from a short prologue, never says a word), the dialogue purports to be part of a trio of conversations set right before the famous trial of Socrates, each of them concerned with defining a different figure: the sophist, the statesman, and the philosopher. But though the Sophist exists, the Philosopher dialogue does not exist (and it is likely that it was never intended to exist); instead, the Sophist is placed in fictional continuity with the Theaetetus, Plato's most important dialogue on knowledge. The conversation itself is delightfully weird. It is full of strange distinctions and odd conclusions (including an elaborate joke about human beings being "featherless bipeds" or "two-legged pigs," which was apparently fodder for ancient pranksters like Diogenes the Cynic), dead ends and mistakes that are extensively discussed and acknowledged within the conversation itself, a long and detailed digression on the art of weaving, and a complex myth about a great "cosmic reversal" of motion in which human beings are depicted as being born from the earth in old age and living their lives in reverse. All of this leads to an ambiguous defense of the rule of law as "second best" and a characterization of the genuine statesman as someone whose main concern is the timing of existential decisions for the polity as a whole, in apparent tension with Plato's classic discussion of the "philosopher king" in the Republic.
The puzzle lies in trying to make sense of how all of these disparate elements (which draw explicit attention both to their ill-fittingness and their fittingness) fit together as a single pedagogical and theoretical exercise; and the book is my attempt to provide a solution to this puzzle that makes sense of the dialogue not merely as a methodological discussion (as most scholars argue) but as a work of political philosophy that is decisively concerned with the question of what "political knowledge" could even mean. I may say more about my answer to this question later (though, as with most Platonic dialogues, most of the fun lies in trying to understand the movement of the conversation rather than in the answers to which the conversation arrives); buy the book (or tell your friendly academic librarian to buy the book) to find out the full version.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)