My previous post, in one chart:
(Click here for larger size).
Bubbles to the right are more democratic countries, measured using the Unified Democracy Scores; bubbles to the left are more autocratic countries. Note how the left side of the graph has much more volatility, even within single countries, as expected; the bubbles move up and down like crazy. By contrast, on the right side of the graph everything oscillates more sedately. (Try following Lebanon, for example; you can also zoom in to particular regions of the graph). For another interesting view, change the color to "regime type" and set the Y axis to plot GDP per capita (rather than GDP per capita growth). (Change the scale to "log," too, for a clearer view).
(Data on economic growth from the Penn World Table.)
Monday, May 21, 2012
Thursday, May 17, 2012
A Very Short Quantitative History of Political Regimes, Part 1.75: Democracy and Development
(Statistician General’s warning: no significance tests or confidence intervals were harmed in the writing of this post. Appropriate model assumptions not guaranteed. Do not use without consulting a trained and licensed statistician.)
I haven’t done one of these posts on the history of political regimes in a while, but I am preparing something for a class on the topic of the relationship between political regimes and economic development, and figured it’s a nice addition to the series. Besides, it is always a good time to put up pretty graphs on this blog.
What is the relationship between political regimes and economic development? The basics of this relationship in the post-WWII era seem pretty well understood: basically, the richer the country, the more likely it is to be “democratic” (in the sense I’ve discussed here and here, where democracy is conceived as a system of normatively regulated competition for control of states including the usual paraphernalia of elections, freedoms of speech and assembly, etc.), though the reasons for why this is the case remain disputed, and there are obvious and significant exceptions to this pattern. Conversely, the academic literature suggests that democratic regimes have a slight and indirect long-term development advantage, though the evidence for this claim is much more controversial, and there is no consensus on how this particular advantage operates, if it exists at all (for a meta-analysis of studies on this topic, see here).
Here I want to look at how the relationship between development and democracy has changed over the past 60 years. For our purposes in this post I am going to use the Unified Democracy Scores developed by Pemstein, Meserve, and Melton. These scores basically aggregate the information contained in nine other democracy scores – Polity IV, DD, Freedom House, and six other lesser known indexes – in such a way as to indicate the “uncertainty” associated with particular country ratings. The score for a given country ranges between around -2 and around 2, with higher numbers being “more democratic.” A score of “zero” can be interpreted as a cut-off between more or less “open” regimes and more or less “closed” regimes, though we could also use three breaks, with regimes at one end of the distribution being clearly “dictatorships,” regimes at the other end being clearly “democratic,” and regimes in the middle being “hybrid” regimes of various kinds – competitive authoritarian, tutelary democracies, democratizing monarchies, etc. As an example, here are the scores for the year 2008, split into three quantiles to indicate
these broad regime categories:
Unified Democracy Scores, 2008 |
(The length of each horizontal line is the 95% confidence
interval for the score; in general, small democracies at the top of the scale have
more uncertain ratings, while dictatorships at the bottom of the scale have narrower
confidence intervals, indicating less disagreement about the classification of
dictatorships than about the determination of the level of democracy beyond a certain point). A
three way split works quite well: the countries in red are the more obvious
dictatorships, while the countries in blue are more clearly democratic, and the
countries in green have the sorts of problematic hybrid regimes that are
difficult to classify with certainty as either wholly democratic or wholly
undemocratic.
Using those breaks, here is what the distribution of regimes
looks like since the 1950s:
Distribution of regime types since 1950 |
Fully closed regimes had their peak in the late 70s and
early 80s, but the end of the Cold War pushed many of these to at least hold
elections, as we saw in
this post. But how has this distribution evolved in terms of income per capita?
Consider this plot:
Income per capita per year and regime type |
(GDP data from the Penn
World Table). Each circle shows the median income of the particular regime
type for a given year, where the size of the circle is proportional to the
number of regimes that fall into that category. The lines show a lowess fit for
the overall trend growth of income for each particular regime type. I interpret
the story the graph tells as follows.
The median income of
democratic regimes has been higher than the median income of both hybrid and
fully authoritarian regimes since at least the 1950s, and the gap has in general
widened, not narrowed, even as the number of democratic countries has
increased. (From this graph we cannot tell, however, whether the gap has
widened because democratic countries have grown faster, or because
non-democratic countries that grew fast turned into democracies; from the graphs below, we may infer that it was a mixture of both). The gap was
highest during “peak authoritarianism” in the late 1970s and early 1980s, when most
poor and newly independent countries were either hybrid regimes or
dictatorships, but it stopped growing after the end of the cold war, when a
number of relatively poor countries became democratic.
Interestingly, whereas before the end of the cold war the median hybrid regime was also richer than the median dictatorship, this pattern is reversed after the end of the cold war. Full authoritarianism proved almost impossible to sustain in poor countries without the patronage of the major powers or natural resource wealth; for the most part only relatively rich dictatorships, or dictatorships that retained a special relationship with a major non-democratic country, survived, whereas most poor countries today have some sort of hybrid regime. Thus in 2008, the list of full dictatorships included Saudi Arabia, North Korea, Myanmar (Burma), Qatar, Libya, Swaziland, Uzbekistan, Turkmenistan, Laos, China, Eritrea, Cuba, UAE, Oman, Equatorial Guinea, Sudan, Iran, and Syria. (Not all of these had GDP data in the Penn World Table – North Korea, for example. Note also that some of these regimes have large levels of uncertainty associated with them – the list could very well have included Brunei, for example, instead of Iran; but the basic point does not appear to change if we switch some of these around. I haven’t really checked, since this is only a blog post and checking requires some actual programming, but one could check by drawing new samples of democracy scores from within the distribution Pemstein, Meserve, and Melton generate. That’s the fun thing about the UD scores. It is also worth noting that some of these regimes appear to have survived the end of the cold war only because they had unifying enemies – Eritrea, Cuba, and Iran come to mind; fear can be just as stabilizing as wealth.)
Interestingly, whereas before the end of the cold war the median hybrid regime was also richer than the median dictatorship, this pattern is reversed after the end of the cold war. Full authoritarianism proved almost impossible to sustain in poor countries without the patronage of the major powers or natural resource wealth; for the most part only relatively rich dictatorships, or dictatorships that retained a special relationship with a major non-democratic country, survived, whereas most poor countries today have some sort of hybrid regime. Thus in 2008, the list of full dictatorships included Saudi Arabia, North Korea, Myanmar (Burma), Qatar, Libya, Swaziland, Uzbekistan, Turkmenistan, Laos, China, Eritrea, Cuba, UAE, Oman, Equatorial Guinea, Sudan, Iran, and Syria. (Not all of these had GDP data in the Penn World Table – North Korea, for example. Note also that some of these regimes have large levels of uncertainty associated with them – the list could very well have included Brunei, for example, instead of Iran; but the basic point does not appear to change if we switch some of these around. I haven’t really checked, since this is only a blog post and checking requires some actual programming, but one could check by drawing new samples of democracy scores from within the distribution Pemstein, Meserve, and Melton generate. That’s the fun thing about the UD scores. It is also worth noting that some of these regimes appear to have survived the end of the cold war only because they had unifying enemies – Eritrea, Cuba, and Iran come to mind; fear can be just as stabilizing as wealth.)
What about growth? Is any particular regime type
consistently associated with economic growth? Here’s what it looks like when we
plot the relative growth performance of different regimes in every year since 1950:
Economic growth by regime type per year |
(Click for a larger version). Each circle represents the
median growth rate for the regime type indicated by the color; the size of the
circle is proportional to the number of regimes in that category for that year.
The lines show a lowess fit of the trend growth rate of each regime type; the
shaded areas represent automatically generated 95% confidence intervals. (Many
caveats apply. See warning above). Any year where the blue circle is higher
than the red or green circles is a year where the median democracy did better
than the median hybrid regime or the median dictatorship.
As indicated by the width of the confidence intervals around
the red and green lines, dictatorships and hybrid regimes have had more
variability in economic performance than democracies since at least the 1950s:
more growth “miracles” and “disasters,” often in the very same country. (See this
paper by William Easterly for the actual scholarly version of the
argument). To the extent that we can ignore these confidence intervals and
focus only on the trend performance, democracies have not always done better
than these other regimes. In the early post-war era it seems that dictatorships
did better (though most did about as well as democracies), but then decolonization
came along and the growth performance of dictatorships basically cratered.
Indeed, the 80s, when the so-called “third wave” of democratization began, was
also (not coincidentally perhaps?) the time when the “growth gap” between
democracies and hybrid and dictatorial regimes was at its widest. Ominously,
the last decade has seen a reversal of this pattern, which explains much of the
(not very well thought out) commentary about the rise of the “Chinese model.” (Democracies,
in particular, seem to have been much more strongly affected by the financial
crisis that started in 2008 than either dictatorships or hybrid regimes, though
all regimes appear to have been affected to some extent). Yet we should not
make too much of this; even in the last decade, democracies did basically the
same as the other regimes, judging by the overlap in confidence intervals –
their responses seem not to have been too obviously wrong relative to the
responses of authoritarian countries (many
of which benefitted from high oil prices). And we should remember that the
median per capita GDP of democracies is already much higher than that of
dictatorships or hybrid regimes; if we ought to be worried about anything, it is
about the effects of bad economic performance on hybrid regimes, which could potentially lead to a
reversion to more authoritarian forms of government:
Economic growth by regime type per year |
I have purposely refrained from making any big claims about
a general relationship between regime
type and economic performance. From the evidence above, it seems that there has
not been a great deal of difference between different regimes, except in the
80s. But instead of throwing away information by breaking the democracy scores
into categories, we could try to look at what the relationship between the raw
scores and growth rates looks like in general. Here’s my idea (please tell me
if this doesn’t work; there are probably a million problems with it I haven't thought about). For every year, we estimate a
simple linear model of the form growth = a*democracy_score + b*log(gdp_per_capita) +
c + error. We then plot the coefficient a for each year; when this coefficient is
positive, the more democratic the country, the better its performance for that
year, adjusting for its existing level of economic development, and when the coefficient
is negative, the opposite is true, i.e., the less democratic the country the better its growth performance for
that year (many caveats apply). When we do this, we find that more democratic
countries had a clear growth advantage only between the mid-1970s and the
mid-1990s, and that advantage seems to have been lost in the 1990s, even
reversed:
(An even simpler model, not controlling for the existing
level of economic development, gives a broader democracy advantage, extending
back to the 1960s, but not a radically different picture.) It is worth noting
that these relationships are different in different regions: the “democracy
advantage” calculated using this method has been negative in East Asia, South
Asia, and Western Europe for the period 1950-2008, and zero or positive just
about everywhere else:
Interestingly, Polynesia, East Africa, and Central Asia have had some of the largest “democracy advantages”: the more democratic the regimes have been there, the better their growth performance. Looking at entire continents, the broadest democracy advantage by far is in Africa (and it is positive in all).(Many caveats apply: for example, there isn’t a lot of variability in the democracy score in some of these regions, like in Australia and New Zealand, and the calculated coefficients aren't always significant).
Anyway, more could be said, but it’s late and I need to move
on. Any thoughts on how to further this sort of analysis? All code needed to
replicate these plots is available here;
you will need to download the Unified Democracy Scores
and the Penn World Table separately.
You also need this
file of country and region codes.
[Update, 18 May: fixed a small mistake in the last two plots. Results don't change, though the Polynesian "democracy advantage" is now more pronounced]
[Update 2, shortly after: I take it back. It was fine the first time, though it doesn't make much difference.]
[Update 2, shortly after: I take it back. It was fine the first time, though it doesn't make much difference.]
Saturday, May 05, 2012
Educational software I wish existed: StackExchange for teaching in the Humanities and Social Sciences
Here’s an idea I’ve been mulling over for the past week.
(Mulling over enough to have spent many hours in an abortive attempt to create
a prototype. But even simple web application programming seems to be a
nontrivial problem that requires more time investment than I can muster right
now). I have a large bank of questions for some of the courses I teach. These
are mostly essay questions (short and long) of varying degrees of complexity, that
ask students to make arguments, provide evidence, point to real-world examples,
etc. I usually select the questions for final exams or other forms of
assessment from this pool; a student who could answer all of them well would
have essentially mastered the content of the course.
I would like to have a web application that draws on this
pool of questions to do this:
- In “quiz mode” a student would either select a question or be served a random question from the pool, and then he/she would answer it. They could then move on to a different question, for as long as they wished. (Perhaps the questions could be served in such a way that students can vote for the questions they most want answered, as in Google Moderator). The software would also allow the students to rate both the quality of their own answers (how good they think their answer is) and/or their level of confidence in their answer (how certain they are that they have a good answer), as well as the level of difficulty of the question. Their answers and ratings would go into a database; as they accumulate, the instructor could see which questions are rated as “hard” by students, or display characteristic problems, and focus teaching efforts there.
- In “rating mode” students would either select a question or be served a random question from the pool, which they would view along with any (anonymized) answers from themselves, other students in the course, or even the instructor. They could then vote on which answer is best (if there is more than one answer) or rate the quality of existing answers. Perhaps they could also comment or edit existing answers if they want to add something to them, or feel a correction is in order. As these ratings accumulate, students would get a better sense of what counts as a good or a bad answer (assuming the “wisdom of crowds” works its magic; the courses I have in mind for this sort of application have around 100 students, which seems like it would be enough).
- In “asking mode,” the application would allow students to submit questions, which then would go into the pool and could be answered by other students in the class. (Administrators could edit the questions for clarity or reject questions that are not sufficiently related to the topic of the course).
- The application could even have something like the reputation management features of the StackExchange family of sites. Students who answer questions would gain reputation “points,” so long as their answers are rated relatively highly (fewer points for unrated or lower-rated answers); asking questions or rating answers would also get them some reputation points, though fewer. (For purely illustrative purposes, imagine that asking a question nets you 2 reputation points, so long as it is not rejected by the instructor, rating an answer nets you 1 point, and answering a question nets you between 5 and 10 points, depending on how highly rated your answers are). Perhaps these reputation points could be translated into actual grade points at the end of the term in accordance with some appropriate formula, though that would depend on the design of the course.
As I imagine it, an application like that would offer
students extensive practice in writing, especially if combined with say, a
requirement that they answer at least one question every week (in fact, this
system could displace one of the traditional two essays we ask students to
complete in many courses). It would also help them practice the entire material
covered in the course: since the questions for the final exam would be drawn
from the pool (or be very similar to some of the questions there) students who
use the tool would be essentially studying for the final every time they use it.
(“Quizzing” yourself is one of the most useful study techniques available, and
the system would be designed so that you would get relatively quick, and
eventually accurate, feedback on your answers, without the instructor having to
grade hundreds of essays). And I (the instructor) would in turn get feedback on
how well they understand the material, as well as on what aspects of the course
they are having difficulty with.
What do people think? What problems would you
foresee emerging with a system like this?
As far as I can tell, nothing quite like that exists, though
in some ways this would be like a private version of StackExchange, seeded with a pool of
questions on some specific course topic and open only to people taking the
course. Google Moderator has some
useful features, and I’ve been thinking about using it as a study tool for students in my
course this term, but it would not be fully integrated with the rest of the
assessment in the way I would want. Or is there something out there that I’m
missing? How difficult would it be to develop the system I've described above?
Saturday, April 28, 2012
The Kantian Logic of Democratization: A Footnote on Levitsky and Way’s Competitive Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes after the Cold War
(A review of Steven Levitsky
and Lucan A. Way’s Competitive Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes
after the Cold War, Cambridge University Press, 2010).
Most political regimes in the world today allow for some
form of electoral competition. As we saw in
this post, towards the end of the cold war most stereotypical
“dictatorships” (where competition by non-official parties was de jure forbidden and political control
over the public sphere was nearly complete) began to give way to regimes in
which control over the state depended in some way on winning real electoral
contests. International pressure from Western powers, the breakdown of the
Soviet Union, and popular protest all contributed to this outcome.
Yet elections, as anyone will tell you, do not equal
democracy. Most of these “electoral” regimes – places like Zimbabwe, Russia,
Romania, Armenia, Georgia, Ghana, Guyana, Kenya, Macedonia, Madagascar,
Nicaragua, and many other countries - featured genuine political competition,
with fiercely contested elections (unlike the meaningless “elections” held in
many communist countries before the end of the cold war), organized oppositions
which often held substantive legislative or subnational offices and could
occasionally even win presidential or parliamentary elections (unlike in de jure one party states), and at least
some islands of media independence (unlike the situation in many genuine
dictatorships); but such competition was neither free nor fair by any
reasonable standard. Incumbents persecuted or harassed their political
opponents by legal or illegal means, intimidated or bought the media, packed
supposedly “independent” judicial institutions with their supporters, used
state resources without restraint for campaign purposes, and even occasionally
fraudulently stole elections through good old-fashioned ballot stuffing and
vote falsification in efforts to secure their position.
Consider a few examples. In Ukraine in the 1990s,
“businesses that financed the opposition were routinely targeted by tax
authorities” and in Ghana similarly “entrepreneurs who financed opposition
parties “were blacklisted, denied government contracts, and [had] their
businesses openly sabotaged”.” In Taiwan, the KMT used to outspend its
opponents 50-1 in elections, and in Russia the Yeltsin campaign spent “between
30 and 150 times the amount permitted the opposition in 1996.” In the Peru of
Fujimori, private television stations “signed “contracts” with the state
intelligence service in which they received up to $1.5 million a month in
exchange for limiting coverage of opposition parties.” (All quotes from Levitsky and Way,
pp. 10-11). Everybody knows about the selective prosecution of potentially
threatening “oligarchs” in Russia (like Mikhail Khodorkovsky)
for tax reasons, not always without some justification (after all, they
probably did not get rich by following
the rules), but the tactic is common, though with local variations according to
context (see, e.g., the Anwar
Ibrahim case in Malaysia). Libel and defamation suits, especially, are the
tool of choice for shutting down critical forms of media: according to Levitsky
and Way, in the nineties newspapers in Croatia were sued for libel more than
230 times; in Cameroon at around the same time the use of defamation suits
forced the closure of several newspapers. (We pass over in silence the use of
libel or defamation suits in Cambodia, Belarus, Russia, and many other places
as a way to intimidate opponents and silence critical voices). Sometimes media
restrictions even get a decent veneer of justification, as when the Chavez
government in Venezuela refused
to renew the “over the air” license of RCTV, an opposition-leaning TV
station, in 2007 for having supported the coup against his government in 2002. All
of these actions are of course made easier if the government takes care to pack
supposedly “impartial” or “independent” institutions (constitutional courts,
electoral commissions, and so on) with government supporters (see, e.g.,
Venezuela and Malaysia). Finally, there are the more obvious tactics to
suppress political competition, to be used when all else fails: beatings and
imprisonment of opposition members by security forces (ask Morgan Tsvangirai and
many other Zanu-PF opponents in Zimbabwe), old-fashioned ballot box stuffing,
and vote falsification (in Serbia under Milosevic, Ukraine under Kuchma, and
many other places).
Rather than thinking of these regimes as somehow imperfect
or transitional democracies, Steven Levitsky and Lucan Way argue that we should
see them as authoritarian regimes in their own right. Levitsky and Way call
them “competitive authoritarian” regimes (a term they coined in a widely cited
2002 article), and tell the story of their emergence and the reasons why
some of them managed to more fully democratize but others did not in a recent
book (Competitive Authoritarianism: Hybrid Regimes
after the Cold War, 2010). The book is a pretty impressive research
achievement; the bibliography alone is 110 pages long, and it can serve as a
good introduction to the post cold war politics of the 35 different countries
they study.[1]
Now, I’d prefer to speak not so much of authoritarianism, democracy, and democratization (at this point at least) but of transformations in the prevalent varieties of political competition in the world. Modern “democracy,” on this view, is merely a system of normatively regulated oligopolistic political competition for state power, which does not sound particularly inspiring, except when we consider how hard it seems to be to achieve even that. In the post cold-war era full political monopolies have tended to decay into systems of unregulated political competition (“competitive authoritarian” or “party hegemonic” regimes) where rulers can often get away with the murder of their political opponents (literally and figuratively); only some of these systems of unregulated political competition turn into modern “democracies,” where rulers cannot so easily get away with murder of their political opponents. So the key question is: how do normatively unregulated systems of political competition turn into normatively regulated ones? How do we move from political systems where rulers “play dirty” by exploiting their control of the state (and oppositions do the same, if they win) to systems where they can’t get away with that, or at least not that easily? (The converse question is also important, though not the focus of Levitsky and Way’s book: why do systems of normatively regulated political competition sometimes break down, leading to regimes where rulers can get away with murder?). The problem is not so much about political turnover (ruling parties do occasionally yield power in competitive authoritarian regimes, even though this typically requires mass protest and other forms of extralegal action as well as winning elections) but about what can shift the kind of political competition that is enabled by a regime.
Levitsky and Way’s answer to that question is relentlessly
structural – protest and opposition action plays little role. It is also
reminiscent of an old argument in Kant’s “Perpetual Peace” (hence the title of
this post; more on that later). In brief, they argue that neither Western
pressure nor domestic opposition action by itself is capable of inducing
democratization (at best, such international and domestic pressure can produce “electoralization,”
not democratization: electoral turnover within normatively unregulated forms of
political competition); it is only when domestic and international pressures
for democracy are consistently amplified by social and economic links with Western
democracies that elites in these regimes will consistently invest in credible ways
of enforcing the norms of political competition (e.g., genuinely independent
electoral commissions and judicial systems, a press that is not constantly pressured
by the government du jour, etc.).
Let’s start with the obvious international pressures for democracy (or political competition, really). Since the end of the cold war most Western powers (at least the powers Levitsky and Way are interested in, the USA and the EU) have adopted an explicit “democratization” agenda, in which they have used various incentives to promote electoral regimes of varying credibility. The effectiveness of these pressures, however, varies with what Levitsky and Way call “leverage,” i.e., the influence Western governments are able to bring to bear on other regimes to make their politics more competitive. Western leverage is greatest for small, aid-dependent countries (like many African countries), and smaller for larger economies (like Mexico or Malaysia). It is larger when democratization is the primary issue on the foreign policy agenda of Western powers (as in many Latin American and Eastern European countries in the 1990s and early 2000s), and smaller when competing issues (like terrorism or other security concerns, especially since 2001) trump democratization (e.g., in the middle East, but also in places like Serbia and Croatia during the Balkan wars), or when other powers are able to provide support to authoritarian rulers (e.g., Russian support for Belarus in the early 1990s, and Chinese support for Burma or North Korea today). It is larger when governments can offer carrots as well as sticks, and smaller when only sticks are available (so the European Union had high democratizing leverage over those countries that were thought to be credible candidates for membership in the EU, but had less leverage over those countries which were unlikely to become members).
Levitsky and Way emphasize that Western pressure for
democratization is very often quite superficial; Western powers are easily
satisfied if the target government conducts more or less “clean” elections, and
sometimes not even that. And they are not always especially consistent; only
salient events, like elections, tend to engage them, whereas more ambiguous actions
like politically motivated prosecutions or the abuse of state resources for
election purposes can pass off uncriticized. (Incidentally, as this neat
new paper by Simpser and Donno argues [gated],
high quality election monitoring can have unintended bad consequences, pushing
competitive authoritarian rulers to use practices that are generally bad for normatively regulating
competition, like muzzling the media or packing the courts as a way of getting
approval for “clean” elections on election day; too much focus on the quality
of elections can thus worsen the quality of the surrounding institutions via
strategic adaptation on the part of incumbent rulers).
Leverage is really helpful for democratization only when it
is reinforced by what Levitsky and Way call linkage.
By this Levitsky and Way mean the whole range of social and economic ties
between Western democracies and competitive authoritarian regimes. These may
include trade and migration links, the circulation of elites through American and
European universities, various forms of communication across borders, and so
on. A high density of these ties helps
produce consistent pressure for
democratization (or rather, for enforcing norms of fair political competition) by
amplifying the effect that even minor
violations of the norms of political competition have on foreign and domestic publics,
creating transnational constituencies for democracy, and providing incentives
for elites in competitive authoritarian states to invest in the credibility of
the institutions for monitoring violations of these norms. It is only when
linkage is high that foreign pressure really becomes expensive for domestic elites in competitive authoritarian regimes,
and not only in purely financial terms; when every suit your government brings against
its political opponents produces an endless stream of NY Times articles,
cancellations of visits from dignitaries, visa troubles, and in general
international opprobrium from their peers and colleagues in Europe or the USA, adherence
to the norms of political competition starts looking like a good deal.
Linkage gets you not only an official EU protest over the
treatment of Yulia Tymoshenko, it gets you a headline like “Europe
Protests Ukraine’s Treatment of Yulia Tymoshenko” in the NY Times, the
promise of an investigation by the Ukrainian government, and Joachim Gauck
cancelling his travel plans to Kiev. I’m sure similar treatment of a Malawian
opposition politician would not have rated anything close to the same reaction.
(And Ukraine, in Levitsky and Way’s scheme, only rates medium, not high, levels
of linkage). Linkage creates lobbies that constantly bring violations of the
norms of political competition to the attention of Western foreign ministries
and legislatures, and it creates elite constituencies interested in preventing such violations in the first
place; it makes Western pressure consistent and predictable. This is why it was
so hard, for example, for Vladimir Meçiar to get away with relatively small
violations of the norms of political competition when he briefly ruled Slovakia
in the 1990s, and why it seems unlikely that Viktor Orban will be able to
consolidate a truly competitive authoritarian regime in Hungary today. By
contrast, when there are few regular ties between a competitive authoritarian
regime and Western democracies, foreign pressure is erratic and constituencies for
enforcing norms of political competition are weak, regardless of the level of
leverage. High leverage and low linkage produces at best electoral turnover (i.e.,
it pushes incumbents out when they lose an election) without genuine
transformations in the norms and institutions of political institutions (the
opposition is likely to be just as bad as the government in its treatment of
the press or its abuse of state resources), which is precisely what Levitsky
and Way think happened in many African countries in the 1990s and early 2000s.
A parallel argument works for domestic sources of pressure, though I think here Levitsky and Way
muddle the presentation of the issues a bit. They want to argue that domestic pressure is usually not that
significant for either democratization or even electoral turnover (in contrast
to some recent scholarship, which emphasizes the importance of protest and
opposition strength). So they emphasize that what really matters is the strength
of states and incumbent party organizations: when these are “strong,” protest
doesn’t get you very far. Milosevic survived enormous levels of mobilization as
long as his security forces held together, whereas in Madagascar or Haiti the
state could barely control the territory, let alone prevent relatively small
opposition forces from overthrowing the government (in Haiti, an “army” of
about 200 rebels). But, as Levitsky and Way sometimes seem to acknowledge, the interesting
question is not so much about turnover
but about the fairness of the norms of competition; and here all the work is
done by linkage, not state or party strength or opposition pressure. Only high
levels of linkage, in their view, induce either victorious oppositions or
incumbent governments to invest in credibly enforcing norms of political
competition; in its absence victorious oppositions do not behave much better
when in power than the governments they displace.
I also think that to speak of “state” vs. “opposition”
strength is to reify the fluid character of these things. One can agree that oppositions
win power in competitive authoritarian regimes where states and incumbent party
organizations splinter (as in the so-called “color revolutions” in the early
2000s), i.e., transfer their loyalty to the opposition or remain neutral, but this
hardly means that opposition efforts don’t matter much: successful opposition
efforts are typically geared towards
inducing such transfers of loyalty. The more interesting point Levitsky and Way
make has to do with why some states
and parties are so resilient in the face of opposition challenges – think of ZANU-PF
in Zimbabwe, holding together in the face of generalized economic collapse and
a well-organized opposition movement. Why? Levitsky and Way point to the role
of non-material incentives: whereas parties and states that are held together
only through patronage (the ability to distribute jobs and benefits) tend to
break down in the face of opposition pressure or economic crisis, security
forces and parties that were forged in war or insurgency (in Armenia or Zimbabwe, for example), or are otherwise held
together by some salient identity in addition to patronage (communism, ethnicity,
etc.), tend to require far more pressure, indeed generational change, to break
down. (This also works for regimes that are not competitive authoritarian but simply monopolize
political competition: Cuba, China, Vietnam, etc.).
There is something “Kantian” about the story Levitsky and
Way tell in this book. In Perpetual Peace
Kant argues that a “federation” of Republican peoples can spread “if a powerful
and enlightened people” that makes itself into a Republic serves as “a fulcrum
to the federation with other states so that they may adhere to it and thus
secure freedom under the idea of the law of nations. By more and more such
associations, the federation may be gradually extended.” This process does not
involve a change in human nature; as Kant says
elsewhere, “from the crooked timber of humanity, no straight thing was ever
made.” All it requires is the growing
interdependence of peoples, which eventually come to acquire interests in
the preservation of republican norms and the maintenance of peace, and which
thus make these republican “cores” grow outwards, slowly. Similarly here: norms
of fair political competition only spread and become powerful through a process
that involves a growing level of interconnectedness across borders. The idea is
simultaneously optimistic – electoralization plus growing connections to the
core (“globalization”?) make the zone of normatively regulated political
competition grow ever outwards – and pessimistic – regimes that are “far” from this
core will have fragile and generally unregulated forms of political competition
regardless (this suggests pessimism about, for example, Mali). (Though they do
not make much of this, their story also suggests that policies that prevent the
growth of linkage – like the “embargo” on Cuba – are about the worst possible
policy to encourage democratization). Of course, this story also assumes that
political competition in the core does not decay, perhaps through processes
that rob it of its importance – think of the growth of the national security
state in the USA, or the ways in which the great recession has affected most
European democracies. But Levitsky and Way tell it pretty convincingly, with
masses of qualitative evidence; I learned a lot from this book.
[1] Albania, Armenia, Belarus, Benin,
Botswana, Cambodia, Cameroon, Croatia, Dominican Republic, Gabon, Georgia,
Ghana, Guyana, Haiti, Kenya, Macedonia, Madagascar, Malawi, Malaysia, Mexico,
Moldova, Mozambique, Nicaragua, Peru, Romania, Russia, Senegal, Serbia,
Slovakia, Taiwan, Tanzania, Ukraine, Zambia, and Zimbabwe. All of these
countries are classified as “Competitive Authoritarian” in 1990-1995; by 2008,
two of them had become “fully authoritarian” (Belarus and Russia), and 14 had
become “full democracies” by Levitsky and Way’s accounting. (One additional
country, Nicaragua, first democratized and then became a competitive
authoritarian regime again by 2008). Their cases do not include countries that
became competitive authoritarian after 1995, or which were “party hegemonic”
regimes in 1995 (too little competition; e.g., Singapore, in their view, though I suspect this case would be problematic for their theory) but
might have become more open since then. They also do not include countries in
which unelected offices are the most important ones, even if there is a
significant electoral component (e.g., Morocco, Iran) or under foreign
occupation.
Wednesday, April 11, 2012
Charles Tilly's Poetry, and the Use of Models in the Social Sciences
In a 1991 review essay discussing several books by James C. Scott, the late Charles Tilly gets cranky with rationalistic explanations of behaviour, in verse ("somehow I find the point easier to make in verse"):
I don't have a lot to say about the quality of the poem - let's say it's better than some, but it's no Dante. (I like the "strands of gold, or silk, or steel, or yet barbed wire" image, for what it's worth - it brings to mind other "strands of gold" images in ancient poetry and nicely reframes them). As for the points Tilly is making - roughly, that most problems of everyday life are computationally intractable, so we "satisfice," and that our intrinsic sociality affects the patterns of social action that we observe - they strike me as unobjectionable in the abstract. But I get the feeling Tilly misunderstands the purpose of models in the social sciences. (I say this with some trepidation - it is far more likely that I am wrong about this than that Tilly misunderstood anything).
As Kevin A. Clarke and David M. Primo have argued in a recent book (and article) models are maps of phenomena. (David Schmidtz has made a similar claim with respect to theories of justice, and I think both draw on the work of the philosopher Ronald Giere). And the most accurate maps are not always the most useful, though it is important that maps be sufficiently similar in some relevant respect to the phenomenon they image for them to be useful. To this I would add that models are also toys ("toy models") and analogies ("metaphors" - Tilly alludes to this in the poem above). They enable certain kinds of rule-constrained "inferential play" (as toys) and disclose or conceal connections to other phenomena (as analogies or metaphors). (They are rhetoric too, qua metaphors, and hence serve persuasive purposes). But let's stick with the map imagery right now. Consider, to use an analogy Clarke and Primo point to, two maps of the London Underground:
Is any of them more "correct"? They are certainly useful for different purposes: they provide different forms of orientation with respect to the tube, and each of them has characteristic failure modes when used for other purposes (to which they may not be well suited). The first map is useful for people who are actually using the train - it helps you visualize the transfers you will need to make, as well as the approximate number of stops left until your destination. But it is not a very good guide to actual distances, and it does not provide any information regarding the urban or natural context of the stations. The second map, while being a more accurate description of the physical organization of the underground and of the urban and topographical context of each station, is much less useful to commuters, who are likely to find it too "busy." Neither of them, it is worth stressing, is a perfectly "accurate" representation of the tube, though both are "similar" to it in some significant respect, enough so that we can speak of them as "representations" of the underground.
Similarly with social science models: economists and (some) political scientists tend to prefer more "abstracted" maps of particular social contexts (like the first map above), since they tend to use such maps for purposes that would not be served by the more apparently "accurate" models that may be favored by sociologists or anthropologists or (other) political scientists (like the second map below). The major methodological disputes in the social sciences thus tend to be (sometimes covertly) about the legitimacy of the purposes for which these maps are used (and only secondarily about whether any particular map does serve any given purpose, though that sort of debate does happen too).
In the poem above, for example, Tilly seems to be saying that the "chess" map of the rationalists (which would surely include economists) is not a good map for making sense of social action because we are not like that. (It is interesting that Tilly also seems to allude to the physicist's map, which depicts social action on the analogy with fluid dynamics, whose laws the fluid particles do not understand but which also makes no reference to individual psychologies, unlike the economist's map). But the "chess" model - the model of rational agents - is not generally a description of our psychology, though it does describe a psychology that is in some respects similar to our actual psychology and in other respects dissimilar. To the extent that rationalistic models of human life are useful (and they may not be, certainly not for every conceivable explanatory purpose) they are not useful because they describe our psychology accurately (though they will be more useful the more the similarities to our psychology in the model are relevant to the explanatory purposes to which it is put), but because they may provide insight into how human action can aggregate into larger patterns (e.g., how markets can sometimes produce efficient outcomes, or how conventions can be self-enforcing), or make certain kinds of predictions (e.g., about when certain norms break down), or identify potential puzzles about social action, or even simply to point to long-term forces pushing social systems in certain directions rather than others. The resulting picture of human action will tend to look (to the anthropologist or the sociologist) like a stick-figure drawing, but that is precisely the point, at least so long as the stick-figure drawing tells us something about human action that is difficult to see in the hyperrealistic map of the anthropologist or the somewhat broader frame of the sociologist.
Social explanation at its best is the art of selecting the right map for orienting ourselves towards some question. In some cases, that map better be quite detailed; if I am interested in getting a real feel for how people distant from me live, or how they can be motivated to rebel against injustice, I am often better off consulting the anthropologists' map than the economist's map. But in other cases, the thickly descriptive map just gets in the way of the particular type of understanding I may be seeking. Even given a certain kind of question, however, some maps will still be better than others. (Some maps give bad directions, or have inconvenient lacunae). In economics, for example, it seems that maps with explicit microfoundations are worse for predictive or policy purposes than maps without such microfoundations, though "microfounded" maps are not thereby useless. In political science, detailed understanding of the politics of particular countries is not necessarily very useful for predictive purposes, though it is certainly very useful for many other purposes. And further problems arise, of course, because fights about methods are also fights about resources and status. The theoretical pluralism of "multiple maps for multiple purposes" tends to break down when certain mapmakers are marginalized, or when there is a perception that particular kinds of maps are being used for purposes to which they are not well suited while serving to attack the status of makers of alternative maps. Somehow I find it easier to make this point in haiku:
Rationalists imagine life as lightning chess,
each individual respecting well-known rules,
instantly sketching alternative scenariosthat start from possible moves, comparingtheir merits, and choosing the wisest meansto maximize the probability of victory,only to see that the opponent is playingthe selfsame game. In such a caricature,few of us can recognize the improvisationsof our cluttered lives. Are we inadequate?
Let's find a betaphore, a better metaphore,for the expedients by which we rush throughthe traps and troubles of an ordinary day.We resemble kayakers, knowing the long streamin which we ride, more or less, but never surewhen its course will bend, speed up, narrow,or thrust us upon rocks and splintered treessavage storms have hurled into the streambed.
In fast white water we often cannot tellwhether we will founder, flip over, crashinto the bank, or hurtle against obstacleswithin the current. When the river slows,we become sentient driftwood, silently glidingat the pace of swans. Or we dig our paddlesinto the depth - one side, then the otherin order to propel our own course past fish,past tributary brooks, past fields of flowers.
The riverbanks exist, our boat exists, we exist,the current's force exists, the boulders exist,and yet we improvise, combining these elementsin quick inventions, and sometimes run aground.
Still, life as a surging kayak ignores the factthat makes the race worth running: the sociabilitythat ties us to other humans and their poor proxiesdogs, cats, and faded photographs - in strandsof gold, or silk, or steel, or yet barbed wire.
Metaphor gives way to metonymy, for our true modelcould be walking through crowds, alone or in pairs,silent or in earnest conversation, at once scanningfaces and facades, feet moving in two-four beats,signaling our approach with glances and swaggers,knifing between oncomers who seem separate or separable.
We follow those pioneers who find an open pathacross the traffic, follow even when another pathwould be shorter, or faster, or easier on the feet.We spot a penny on the sidewalk, a gown in a window,or a broken hydrant while the interior monologue hums,the exterior dialogue swirls, the frantic tinkeringof every day continues. A cameraman above shoots filmand charts human beings as molecules in a channel,lawfully accelerating and slowing according to density,flowing symmetrically around those talkers who stopprecisely in midpath, walkers miming viscous fluidswhose laws they do not know. Meanwhile we pedestrians
("Domination, Resistance, Compliance... Discourse," Sociological Forum 6(3), p. 602). To which my first reaction was: WTF? Also: is this the only use of a poem to make an argument in sociology or political science? Are there others? (James C. Scott apparently promised a poem in "his next review" of Tilly's work - does anybody know if the promise was kept?).dream, improvise, weave, stumble, curse, above all, hope.
I don't have a lot to say about the quality of the poem - let's say it's better than some, but it's no Dante. (I like the "strands of gold, or silk, or steel, or yet barbed wire" image, for what it's worth - it brings to mind other "strands of gold" images in ancient poetry and nicely reframes them). As for the points Tilly is making - roughly, that most problems of everyday life are computationally intractable, so we "satisfice," and that our intrinsic sociality affects the patterns of social action that we observe - they strike me as unobjectionable in the abstract. But I get the feeling Tilly misunderstands the purpose of models in the social sciences. (I say this with some trepidation - it is far more likely that I am wrong about this than that Tilly misunderstood anything).
As Kevin A. Clarke and David M. Primo have argued in a recent book (and article) models are maps of phenomena. (David Schmidtz has made a similar claim with respect to theories of justice, and I think both draw on the work of the philosopher Ronald Giere). And the most accurate maps are not always the most useful, though it is important that maps be sufficiently similar in some relevant respect to the phenomenon they image for them to be useful. To this I would add that models are also toys ("toy models") and analogies ("metaphors" - Tilly alludes to this in the poem above). They enable certain kinds of rule-constrained "inferential play" (as toys) and disclose or conceal connections to other phenomena (as analogies or metaphors). (They are rhetoric too, qua metaphors, and hence serve persuasive purposes). But let's stick with the map imagery right now. Consider, to use an analogy Clarke and Primo point to, two maps of the London Underground:
From Knightsbridge.net |
From A Welsh View |
Similarly with social science models: economists and (some) political scientists tend to prefer more "abstracted" maps of particular social contexts (like the first map above), since they tend to use such maps for purposes that would not be served by the more apparently "accurate" models that may be favored by sociologists or anthropologists or (other) political scientists (like the second map below). The major methodological disputes in the social sciences thus tend to be (sometimes covertly) about the legitimacy of the purposes for which these maps are used (and only secondarily about whether any particular map does serve any given purpose, though that sort of debate does happen too).
In the poem above, for example, Tilly seems to be saying that the "chess" map of the rationalists (which would surely include economists) is not a good map for making sense of social action because we are not like that. (It is interesting that Tilly also seems to allude to the physicist's map, which depicts social action on the analogy with fluid dynamics, whose laws the fluid particles do not understand but which also makes no reference to individual psychologies, unlike the economist's map). But the "chess" model - the model of rational agents - is not generally a description of our psychology, though it does describe a psychology that is in some respects similar to our actual psychology and in other respects dissimilar. To the extent that rationalistic models of human life are useful (and they may not be, certainly not for every conceivable explanatory purpose) they are not useful because they describe our psychology accurately (though they will be more useful the more the similarities to our psychology in the model are relevant to the explanatory purposes to which it is put), but because they may provide insight into how human action can aggregate into larger patterns (e.g., how markets can sometimes produce efficient outcomes, or how conventions can be self-enforcing), or make certain kinds of predictions (e.g., about when certain norms break down), or identify potential puzzles about social action, or even simply to point to long-term forces pushing social systems in certain directions rather than others. The resulting picture of human action will tend to look (to the anthropologist or the sociologist) like a stick-figure drawing, but that is precisely the point, at least so long as the stick-figure drawing tells us something about human action that is difficult to see in the hyperrealistic map of the anthropologist or the somewhat broader frame of the sociologist.
Social explanation at its best is the art of selecting the right map for orienting ourselves towards some question. In some cases, that map better be quite detailed; if I am interested in getting a real feel for how people distant from me live, or how they can be motivated to rebel against injustice, I am often better off consulting the anthropologists' map than the economist's map. But in other cases, the thickly descriptive map just gets in the way of the particular type of understanding I may be seeking. Even given a certain kind of question, however, some maps will still be better than others. (Some maps give bad directions, or have inconvenient lacunae). In economics, for example, it seems that maps with explicit microfoundations are worse for predictive or policy purposes than maps without such microfoundations, though "microfounded" maps are not thereby useless. In political science, detailed understanding of the politics of particular countries is not necessarily very useful for predictive purposes, though it is certainly very useful for many other purposes. And further problems arise, of course, because fights about methods are also fights about resources and status. The theoretical pluralism of "multiple maps for multiple purposes" tends to break down when certain mapmakers are marginalized, or when there is a perception that particular kinds of maps are being used for purposes to which they are not well suited while serving to attack the status of makers of alternative maps. Somehow I find it easier to make this point in haiku:
maps are different
but mapmakers are prickly
and love their maps best(Ok, not a very good haiku. I'm sure you can do better.)
Thursday, April 05, 2012
The Limits of Protest in Complex Societies
(I’ve been invited by the Society for Philosophy
and Culture here at VUW to host a session
of their Symposiumon “Protest” on 5 April. I have taken this as an opportunity to try to
figure out what I think about protest in general, and to speculate wildly on a
bunch of related themes. Also, a riot of mixed metaphors)
Dissatisfaction with the social and
political world can take many forms – everything from resignation and escape to
covert resistance and sabotage to full-blown collective action. It is only
sometimes that such dissatisfaction expresses itself as what we have come to
understand as protest: collective public action that aims for
social or political change. The past year has seen a great global
wave of protest movements, among which the Arab Uprisings and the Occupy Wall
Street movement are only the most well known. But what can protest accomplish
in highly complex societies? What are the limits of protest?
Protest takes many forms: the repertoire
of protest is large, and is constantly being re-invented in local idioms and adjusted to local circumstances. Some protests make clear “demands”
on specific authorities; others enact their dissatisfaction in more or less
spectacular ways, or refuse to speak with one voice. Some forms of protest are
meticulously planned and organized; others happen spontaneously, taking
advantage of very temporary circumstances, and are as much of a surprise to
participants as to the putative targets of the protest. Protesters have
pursued all sorts of goals, from the liberatory to the repressive. Yet all
protest is ultimately a form of voice (in contradistinction to
exit, in
Albert Hirschmann’s famous scheme). And voice generally has two dimensions:
an instrumental dimension, and an expressive or communicative dimension. (I am tempted to say: there are locutionary, illocutionary, and perlocutionary dimensions to protest, but that would complicate things needlessly).
Instrumentally, protest is (roughly) a form
of coordinated public action that uses diverse tactics to put pressure on specific
institutions to address particular problems or issues in more or less specific
ways. (We should understand the tactics of protest very broadly: "symbolic" action - including, for example, sharing a video or wearing certain clothing - can be part of the repertoire of protest.) From this perspective, the success of protest is measured by the degree
to which it forces these institutions to respond to the problems or issues in
question in accordance with the claims or values articulated by protesters.
Protest can (sometimes) do this because it can signal changes
in the support of members of political coalitions within particular
institutions, or in the commitment of important actors to
support these coalitions; it can turn the attention of
powerful actors within institutions towards the problems raised by participants
in protest; it can communicate information about potential
solutions acceptable to influential coalition members; and in general can shift public
discourse in ways that frame the concerns of the protesters in favourable ways.
These are not the only things that protests can do, but they are the main
things that matter for the instrumental success of protest. (For example,
protest can sometimes directly create or destroy institutions,
but in general it is best to conceive of protest as acting on institutions
rather than generally creating or destroying them. More on this point below.)
Consider the protests in Egypt that forced
Mubarak from power. How did a relatively small proportion of the population
occupying in a mostly nonviolent manner a variety of public spaces succeed in
overthrowing a ruler who had been in power for over 30 years and was apparently
backed by the USA and a professional military force? The protests did not
threaten him physically; rather, they provided the opportunity for members of
Mubarak’s coalition of influential supporters to reconsider their support of
the old dictator. The very costly signal of commitment given by the crowds
assembled for 17 days at Tahrir (and elsewhere), bringing the country to a
halt, probably made the upper echelons of the army recalculate the costs and benefits of
standing with Mubarak (and having to potentially direct soldiers of uncertain reliability to massacre the assembled crowds). The protests further
focused the country's attention budget on a single, specific issue (who should
be in control of the state) and framed the problem in a way that was favorable
to protesters. Finally, the fact that the protestors had articulated a clear,
unifying demand (Mubarak must go) made it possible in turn for the members of
Mubarak’s coalition to respond in ways that would defuse the protest. Yet
though this was no mean achievement, it is obvious that 17 days of concentrated
mass action (with longer roots - there was a lot of preparatory work before those 17 days) are hardly sufficient to completely reconstitute the institutions
of the Egyptian state, not just shifting elite coalitions. I do not mean to
imply that many people believed that they would, though some of the rhetoric
coming from participants and supporters of the Egyptian uprising sometimes gave
that impression; only that we need to understand the fundamental limitations of
protest as an instrument of social and political change.
I can think of at least three important
limitations. The first is perhaps the most obvious: though, as I noted above,
the protest repertoire is large and protesters constantly innovate (the
Egyptian protests succeeded in part because of innovative
ways of deceiving the police, building up a movement, and identifying promising political opportunities), they are in a race with other actors who are
not sitting tight. Develop a tactic that exploits a vulnerability in the
political opportunity structure – like the “Occupy” tactic we have seen spread
in the past year – and opponents on the other side of the issue will often
enough develop something that, if it doesn't entirely counteract the
effectiveness of your tactic, will certainly render it less effective. Revolutionaries
are creative, but dictators can be too. Technology can give a temporary advantage to one side rather
than another, but these advantages rarely last: Facebook and Twitter can help protesters
organize, but they can also help opponents track protesters down and infiltrate
them. Among the only generalizations that we can make with any certainty is that during the last century "nonviolent" tactics (of which there is an enormous variety) seem to have worked better (and produced better ultimate outcomes) than "violent" tactics to produce political change even in highly repressive contexts. (We are talking here about protest from a purely instrumental point of view; non-violent protest may well be normatively justified in other ways). But in the long run, I suspect the advantage remains resolutely with
the defence: states and large institutions typically have resources
that allow them, if nothing else, to wait you out or overpower you, as long as those at the top can learn from the mistakes of others.
To be sure, resourceful and creative protest organizers can create new opportunities, while lumbering institutions are sometimes slow to react. As in "regular" warfare, raw
numbers and luck sometimes count for more than tactics. But there is no known protest method that can systematically grow a movement and be invulnerable to all counter-tactics, no “nuclear bomb” ensuring unconditional
institutional surrender. In the long run, all protest tactics can be
counteracted by some counter-tactic, and every counter-tactic in turn will be likely rendered ineffective eventually; hence the advantages of second-comers (Egypt) where protest movements can learn from first-comers who demonstrate the viability of particular protest methods (Tunisia), but the disadvantages of late-comers (Syria) where regimes have observed ways to foil these tactics. More importantly, there is no protest tactic that can ultimately reconstitute the whole of society if only enough people joined in - no grand general strike that can put an end to the system once and for all. Great social movement protest campaigns
are thus typically hard slogs, not lighting victories; they can last many years
(indeed, the uprising in Egypt had roots in movements going back a decade or
so, and many failed actions through which a movement was built and much was learned), and at the end of the day they only
steer the great ship of state slowly in one direction rather than another. (The image of the ship of state is very old - as old as Plato in Western political thought - but it can still serve as a useful analogy for social and political change: if society is like a supertanker, significant political change requires immense energies to turn it around even a little, but too much pressure - civil war, etc. - occasionally breaks the ship and sinks it, spilling the toxic waste all over the place.)
The second important instrumental
limitation of protest is also pretty obvious, and has to do with the scarcity of the most important
resource that voice requires to be effective: time (or, more specifically, coordinated
time). Protest works to focus attention; it concentrates the diffuse and
uncoordinated dissatisfaction of many into a unified chorus, and amplifies this
dissatisfaction in ways that attract the attention of publics that might share
some of these dissatisfactions, and of political coalitions that can act to change
the circumstances giving rise to them. But in the short run, the attention
budget for all issues of interest is limited; attention can be shifted, not
created, since we are a finite number of human beings who live only a finite
amount of time. So protesting X means not protesting Y; and protesting X means
not doing A, B, and C, at least for the duration of the protest. There is
always some other pressing issue that
loses out in the competition for attention, some other problem that could be plausibly argued to be more important: to protest is to make a claim about the proper priorities of an institution.
(But how could we know?).
Of course, sometimes X and Y can be subsumed under Z: instead of protesting the gender gap in pay or racism in some particular institution, people protest inequality in general, or capitalism, or the system. But insofar as the effectiveness of protest depends on its ability to shift support within political coalitions, it should be more effective when the "solution" to a problem depends on shifts within one or a few such coalitions (e.g., when it is a matter of of dumping a dictator) than when it depends on untangling multiple coalitions in complex networks of institutions (e.g., when the problem is to democratize an entire society). The best protest can do for more complex problems is to trigger shifts in public discourse ("put things on the agenda") that in turn may catalyze forms of deliberation and "social cognition" capable of generating useful ideas about how to unravel these knots (without resorting to the classic Gordian solution with its attendant violence). And here the communicative or expressive dimension of protest also plays a role: a protest brings forth a public and induces a conversation within it, even if the conversation often leads in directions neither planned nor approved by the protesters.
Here it is also worth noting a difference between protests and institutions. Institutions as it were "store" coordinated action and constantly regenerate it as they use it for specific purposes (but they can squander it if they use it for purposes for which they are not well designed); a protest, by contrast, is always in danger of exhausting its fuel supply. A protest discharges its forces like a battery or perhaps a capacitor; an institution is more like a generator, capable of powering complex circuits of action for longer periods of time to act on complex problems. This is why it makes sense that protests are often directed at institutions, but also why their effects can be so ephemeral. Long protest campaigns can at best transform movements into institutions, continually regenerating the possibility of protest as coordinated action (consider classic human rights institutions like Amnesty International). But instrumentally effective protests will normally tend to simplify and narrow the focus of collective action – to paper over differences of opinion and interest among participants and focus on specific, clearly articulable and above all simple messages that economize on the "coordination energies" necessary to keep the movement together, like the demand that Mubarak step aside; and they will become less effective as the problems they tackle increase in complexity (involving more tangled coalitions of people) and their potential solutions impact participants in more complicated ways. Local protests about issues that are of concrete significance to participants and where key political coalitions are well known will thus tend to be more effective than protests about global, diffuse and complex problems where it is not even clear which political coalitions should be the targets of action (e.g., protests about global warming).
This is connected to the third important limitation of protest. Effective protest tends to run on simple moral narratives, because human beings tend to be energized to act collectively by simple moral narratives, and protests that do not articulate simple moral narratives will ceteris paribus mobilize fewer people; but the world does not run on simple moral narratives (especially not modern complex societies with many only vaguely visible and poorly understood interdependencies). Protest is often very effective for making dictators leave power, but it is only marginally useful for ensuring that a constitution makes sense, and it is much easier to coordinate large numbers of people to do something about "bad guys" than to coordinate them in ways that will make a lasting difference to complex problems. (There is probably an evolutionary reason for this). Consider the example of the Kony #2012 video: a simplistic moral narrative was able to mobilize millions of people in symbolic solidarity against a bad guy (and perhaps shift the agenda within powerful institutions), but it is highly unlikely that such action will produce lasting and significant positive change where it matters most (though in the best case it may get people involved with local groups in Northern Uganda, and perhaps to learn more about complex problems).
None of this is to say that because protest has limits, it should not be used. Far from it! Social change of any kind is hard; but protest, as a form of voice, is only one potential method of change. (Various forms of exit are also important; and the parallel building of institutions - starting a new society in place of the old - is also a time-honored way of acting in the world). Moreover, protest should not be viewed only in instrumental terms. Protest at its best opens up public spaces of appearance, where people can experience the joy of acting together, as Hannah Arendt put it. It is expressive as well as instrumental, and there is nothing wrong with that: protest can be a tactic and a party.
[Update 4/6/2012: minor typo fixes]
[Update 2, 4/7/2012: fixed errant pronouns, link]
Tuesday, March 27, 2012
Crowdsourcing a Democracy Index – 2012 edition
It’s that time of the year again – time to crowdsource a
democracy index.
First, a bit of context. Last year, I had the idea of using the
Allourideas pairwise comparison software
to crowdsource a ranking of countries by their degree of “democracy” in 2010. I
asked students in my Dictatorships and Revolutions class to set the ball
rolling, and then posted the link to the widget here, allowing anybody to
vote. Surprisingly, in just a couple of months of voting the
results were interestingly close to standard indexes of freedom or democracy:
the crowdsourced ranking had a correlation of 0.84 with Freedom House’s
widely-used ratings
of political and civil liberties for 2010, and the basic crowdsourced
ranking was generally plausible (see this
post for further analysis of these results) . In fact, by now the correlation has increased
to 0.86 (8556 votes total), which is about as good the correlation between Freedom House and Polity IV (0.87).
I am interested in seeing if this kind of crowdsourced
measure can be used as a sort of quick and dirty index of democracy. To be
sure, crowdsourcing the construction of an index of democracy in this way is usually
not a good way of generating reliable social science data. For one thing, the
exercise does not impose any restrictions on how the concept of “democracy”
should be understood, which means that it implicitly aggregates all kinds of
different ideas about democracy, weighting them by the degree to which larger
numbers of people consider them important. (It takes a “democratic” approach to
concept formation, you might say). But it does have the virtue of being cheap (total
cost: about $0, compared to over US$500,000 annually for the Freedom House “Freedom
in the World” report, and $120,000 annually for the Polity IV project), aggregating
the dispersed information of large numbers of people from all over the world,
and making it possible to generate various measures of “uncertainty” around the
crowdsourced estimates. So I want to repeat the exercise, and produce a
democracy ranking for 2011:
(Click here if you can’t see
the widget above. Vote as many times as you'd like, and don't worry if you have to use the "I can't decide" button).
In theory, the more votes, and the more diverse the voting
population – the more people from Africa, Latin America, Asia, and the rest of
the world – the more informative the results should be. So please vote early
and often, and share!
I am also interested in which dimensions of the
complex concept of democracy people tend to weigh more when making these
sorts of comparisons. Do people put more weight on the presence or absence of
elections, for example, than on economic equality? You can help me to figure this out by using the
widget below to rank various dimensions or components of democracy in terms
of their importance to you (or adding your own):
(Click here if you can’t
see the widget above. Vote as many times as you'd like, and don't worry if you have to use the "I can't decide" button).
The “seed” dimensions of democracy for these comparisons are
taken from a recent piece by Michael Coppedge, John Gerring, et al. (“Conceptualizing
and Measuring Democracy”, Perspectives
on Politics 9(2): pp. 42-62; ungated
here) that is very much worth reading if you are interested in the issue of
how to measure democracy. But I make no claim that these are the only dimensions of democracy that
matter; if people have other ideas, you can add them in (I will need to approve
any suggestions, though). You are also
welcome to discuss in comments the kinds of considerations that you used to make
distinctions between countries, or any other considerations that might improve the usefulness of this sort of exercise.
Enjoy, and please share!
Thursday, March 22, 2012
The Irrelevance of Legitimacy - now as a working paper!
(This paper has now been published. The official version is available here, and an ungated version can be found here).
Sorry for the recent silence. I've been busy with administrative tasks, the beginning of the term here in the Southern hemisphere, and indexing a book. I've also been working on a paper: "The Irrelevance of Legitimacy":
Most of the arguments in the paper will be familiar to readers of this blog; in fact, many began life as blog posts (see, e.g., here, here, here, and here), though the paper ties them together and explicates them more carefully. Responses to these posts convinced me that there was something there worth researching more fully and discussing in more detail, and I want to thank readers and commenters for feedback and encouragement. Comments on the paper are also welcome; it is still work in progress (the final section, in particular, still needs a great deal of work, but every part of the argument could be tightened and subject to careful scrutiny, and will likely change a great deal before the paper gets submitted to actual peer review).
The main ideas of the paper were motivated by my dissatisfaction with the Weberian dictum (almost a cliche at this point) that power needs to be legitimated in order to endure. Though relationships of domination are often embedded within justificatory discourses, my view is that we cannot in general explain the stability of such relationships by pointing to the genuine acceptance of such justifications by the subordinate. (As I note in the paper, Weber himself seemed to be aware of this point, if inconsistently; he notes that all that matters for the stability of relationships of domination is that the claim to legitimacy be taken as valid, not that it be believed, and these are two very different things). To say that power needs legitimacy in order to endure is at best to say that power needs credible commitments in order to endure, and discourses of justification typically provide the language in which such credible commitments are expressed and measured; they are the form, not the cause of the stability of power. The title is nevertheless a bit of an exaggeration; a more appropriate title might have been "the limited relevance of legitimacy," since I admit that there are some conditions (primarily cases where exit or voice constraints on a relationship are minimal) where appeals to legitimacy have some explanatory and normative force, but I decided to go for broke. Anyway, I would be grateful for any feedback. Enjoy!
Your irregularly scheduled blogging will resume shortly.
Sorry for the recent silence. I've been busy with administrative tasks, the beginning of the term here in the Southern hemisphere, and indexing a book. I've also been working on a paper: "The Irrelevance of Legitimacy":
The concept of legitimacy plays an important explanatory and normative role in political theory and political discourse. The idea is typically used both to explain the stability of a political order by pointing to acceptance of discursive justifications for that order, and to evaluate its normative appropriateness by comparing the conditions of the actual acceptance of discourses of justification to the conditions of their rational acceptability. The normative and explanatory roles of the concept of legitimacy are linked insofar as actual acceptance of justificatory discourses is usually taken to be (defeasible) evidence for their rational acceptability. I argue here that legitimacy (in the sense of acceptance of discursive justifications for political order) is generally irrelevant for the explanation of political stability: if anything, stability explains legitimacy rather than the other way around. Stability is in turn best explained by the way in which signals of commitment are generated through collective action, not by pointing to the individual acceptance of discursive justifications for political order. I illustrate the inadequacy of explanations of political order in terms of legitimacy by examining the phenomenon of cults of personality in totalitarian regimes, and raise some questions about the normative utility of the concept given its explanatory irrelevance. (Link to download).I'll be presenting a shortened version of this paper at the Midwest Political Science Association meeting in Chicago on April 13.
Most of the arguments in the paper will be familiar to readers of this blog; in fact, many began life as blog posts (see, e.g., here, here, here, and here), though the paper ties them together and explicates them more carefully. Responses to these posts convinced me that there was something there worth researching more fully and discussing in more detail, and I want to thank readers and commenters for feedback and encouragement. Comments on the paper are also welcome; it is still work in progress (the final section, in particular, still needs a great deal of work, but every part of the argument could be tightened and subject to careful scrutiny, and will likely change a great deal before the paper gets submitted to actual peer review).
The main ideas of the paper were motivated by my dissatisfaction with the Weberian dictum (almost a cliche at this point) that power needs to be legitimated in order to endure. Though relationships of domination are often embedded within justificatory discourses, my view is that we cannot in general explain the stability of such relationships by pointing to the genuine acceptance of such justifications by the subordinate. (As I note in the paper, Weber himself seemed to be aware of this point, if inconsistently; he notes that all that matters for the stability of relationships of domination is that the claim to legitimacy be taken as valid, not that it be believed, and these are two very different things). To say that power needs legitimacy in order to endure is at best to say that power needs credible commitments in order to endure, and discourses of justification typically provide the language in which such credible commitments are expressed and measured; they are the form, not the cause of the stability of power. The title is nevertheless a bit of an exaggeration; a more appropriate title might have been "the limited relevance of legitimacy," since I admit that there are some conditions (primarily cases where exit or voice constraints on a relationship are minimal) where appeals to legitimacy have some explanatory and normative force, but I decided to go for broke. Anyway, I would be grateful for any feedback. Enjoy!
Your irregularly scheduled blogging will resume shortly.
Friday, March 02, 2012
On stability and legitimacy
Consider the following passages from David Beetham’s The
Legitimation of Power (1991):
…it is a notable feature of power
relations that they are themselves capable of generating the evidence needed
for their own legitimation. Thus the evidence of superiority and inferiority
which justifies the inequality of condition between dominant and subordinate is
itself largely the product of that condition. Those who are excluded from key
positions, activities or resources are thereby denied the opportunity to
acquire or demonstrate the capacities and characteristics appropriate to their
occupation or exercise, so justifying their subordinate position. This is true
even where relatively open processes of selection are at work, once the
selection is performed by an educational system which is given the task of
preparing children differentially for their respective future roles. Evidence
about the fitness or appropriateness of people to exercise power thus tends to
be structured by the relations of power themselves, and therefore to have a
self-fulfilling quality about it.
The same holds true for
demonstrations of the general interest. Once some necessary social resource or
activity comes to be controlled by a particular group, it follows that the
interests of society at large can only be met through satisfying the interests
of that group, and on terms acceptable to them. (pp. 60-61)
[…]
The capacity of power structures
to generate the evidence necessary to their own justification, and to reproduce
the conditions of dependency from which consent to subordination is freely
given, helps to explain how it is that their legitimacy can come to be widely
acknowledged by those involved in them, the subordinate included. ‘Dominant
ideology’ theories tend to put far too much emphasis upon the determining
influence exercised by the powerful over the ideas of the subordinate, through
their preferential access to the means of ideological construction and
dissemination … The account offered here suggests a different kind of
explanation: that both the evidence and the interests of the subordinate that
the justifications advanced for the rules of power prove plausible to them
within the given social context. Their plausibility can only be challenged from
a position or standpoint outside that context, e.g. by comparison with
alternative rules of power, or when social changes have come to undermine from
within the evidence on which they are based. (p. 62)
I think this is pretty insightful, though I still want to
take issue with it. Basically, what Beetham is arguing is that to the extent
that subordinate groups willingly accept their position within large-scale
systems of domination (e.g., to the extent that women accept a subordinate
position to men in patriarchal societies, peasants to landlords in an agrarian
societies, low-caste groups in caste societies, or for that matter
disenfranchised people in a dictatorships or workers under capitalism) this is not primarily because they are duped by the propaganda of the dominant (the
classic “false consciousness” explanation), but rather because the operation of
the system makes the claims of the dominant – their claims to greater skill,
intelligence, effort, care for the common good, etc. – generally plausible. People will accept the propaganda of the
powerful only if (and so long as) it is not obviously in conflict with their everyday
experience; and a system will remain legitimate
only so long as it works to reduce the gap between the lived experience of people
in subordinate positions and the justificatory rhetoric of the powerful by
producing systematic evidence that
the claims of the powerful are plausible, even true, at least within the
context of shared categories of interpretation (which may themselves be structurally
biased to favour the views of the powerful). Moreover, given the plausibility of these claims, it will
make sense for the subordinate to pursue their interests within the terms set
by the system.
It is worth stressing that Beetham does not argue that this
is always the case in every social
system. Not every social system is experienced as legitimate; and those which
are not experienced as legitimate are
precisely those where the subordinate can perceive an obvious gap between the
qualities or actions the powerful say justify their position and the qualities
they actually have, or between the possibilities for pursuing their interests
given within the system and possibilities obviously available elsewhere. Moreover,
his argument only applies to
large-scale social systems. Small-scale relations of domination could not systematically generate the evidence
necessary for their own justification; they must “borrow” it from the larger
scale system within which they are embedded. For example, in a highly
patriarchal society the claims of men for their
own position – claims based on education, experience, etc. that are themselves
differentially allocated - will only be generally
plausible to women; exceptions will abound, and within particular relations it will not always make sense for women to
“accept” subordinate positions. (There are a lot of nuances and complications
packed into the term “accept,” but let that pass for the moment). If women experience
this system as legitimate, it will not necessarily be because of their individual “micro-experience,” so to speak, but
because their understanding of “normative” facts (that is, their understanding
of what is “normal”) tells them that in general women are less educated, have
fewer of the relevant qualities for rule, etc., and that given those facts it will be easier to pursue their interests
within the terms set by men.
Yet I think Beetham still puts too much stress on belief as a way to explain stability and
pays too little attention to the constraints that opportunities for exit and
collective action impose on these same beliefs. If anything, stability explains belief, rather than
the other way around. To say that a legitimate system is stable, I want to
suggest, is merely to express a tautology: systems of domination that are believed to be stable (even if this belief
exists only because, for example, no one can coordinate large numbers on specific
alternatives) will (most of the time) produce beliefs rationalizing the legitimacy of the system.
Consider the question of why repressive dictatorships invest
so much effort in monopolizing the public sphere and policing the “attention
economy.” The problem such regimes face is not
that the majority of the people fail to believe the justificatory rhetoric
of the rulers now (though they may or
may not!), but that whatever they believe now
cannot stabilize the regime in the
absence of the regime’s efforts to monopolize the public sphere; if their justificatory
claims were self-evidently true, they would not
require policing the public sphere in the same way. These regimes can close
the gap between their justificatory claims and the experience of the people
subject to them only by credibly
threatening to punish those who might want to break their monopoly over the
discourse of justification. It is only when the system is believed to be
stable – that is, when the threats to those who would like to break the state’s
monopoly over the public sphere are deemed to be most credible – that people
will be most likely to adaptively accept the claims of the powerful.
One might also point to a number of experiments (ungated) that suggest that it is precisely when a constraint is experienced as inevitable or absolute that people are most likely to accept it, whereas when they experience the constraint as somehow not quite as absolute – perhaps because they see a way of changing it or resisting it that they are most likely to reject it.What
matters causally, in other words, is the belief in stability rather than the belief in the justifications for the relation of domination; absent the belief in
stability, the belief in the justifications also goes.
Or consider the case of the dalits in India, as described in a short piece I came across
recently by Shikha Dalmia. The caste system endures even
where formal institutions do not enforce it; it is an informal equilibrium which
the dalits themselves help to perpetuate. But why? Dalmia notes that an individual dalit will often do best by
abiding by the rules of the caste system:
How? Consider Maya’s story.
Maya assigned herself to our
house in 1977. We had no choice. If we wanted our trash picked up, bathrooms
scrubbed and yards cleaned, Maya was it. Indians find dealing with other
people’s refuse not just unpleasant, but polluting. Hence only dalits are
willing to do this work, something that both stigmatizes them and gives them a
stranglehold on the market. And they have transformed this stranglehold into an
ironclad cartel that closes all other options for their customers.
When Maya got married at 16, her
father-in-law paid another dalit $20 for her wedding gift: the “rights” to
service 10 houses in our neighborhood, including ours. Maya has no formal deed
to these “rights,” yet they are more inviolable than holy writ. Maya’s fellow
dalits, who own the “rights” to other houses, can’t work in hers, just as she
can’t work in theirs.
Doing so, Maya insists, would be
tantamount to theft that would invite a well-deserved beating and ostracism by
the dalit community. No one would help a “poacher” or attend her family
functions like births, weddings or funerals.
This arrangement has guaranteed
Maya a monthly income of $100 that, along with her husband’s job as a “gofer”
at a government lab, has helped her raise three children and build a modest
house with a bathroom, a prized feature among India’s poor. But Maya’s monopoly
doesn’t give her just money. It also hands her clout to resist the upper-caste
power structure, not always for noble reasons.
None of Maya’s employers dares
challenge her work. Maya takes more days off for funerals every year than there
are members in her extended family. Complaining, however, is not only pointless
but perilous. It would result in stinking piles of garbage outside the
complainer’s home for days. Every time my mother gets into spats with Maya over
her sketchy scrubbing, my mother loses. One harsh word, and Maya boycotts our
house until my mother cajoles her back. Nor is Maya the only sweeper, or
jamadarni, with an attitude. All of New Delhi is carved up among Maya-style
sweeper cartels and it is a rare house whose jamadarni is not a “big problem.”
This is consistent with Beetham’s story: Maya accepts her
position within the caste system (to the extent that “accept” is the right word
for what is going on, but let’s pass that over) because she finds that it is plausibly in her individual interest to do so,
though collectively this results in a bad outcome for all dalits, including
social segregation, lack of mobility, etc. (Prisoner’s dilemmas everywhere!).
But it is plausibly in her interest to accept her position because opportunities both for collective action to change the system and
for exiting the relationship are thought to be unlikely; the collective
action or exit constraint is prior to
Maya’s first-order beliefs about her caste position, which would easily change if these collective constraints and exit opportunities changed, as we can glimpse near
the end of the story:
Maya is resigned to such
discrimination, but not her oldest son, 36. He holds a government job, works as
a sales representative for an Amway-style company and dreams big. He is
embarrassed by his mother and lies to his customers about her work. He makes
enough money to support Maya and wants her to quit, but she will have none of
it. She fears destitution and poverty more, she says, than she craves social
respectability.
But the choice may not be hers
much longer.
Upon retirement, she had planned
to either pass her “business” to her children or sell it to another dalit for
about $1,000. But about six months ago, municipal authorities started
dispatching vans, Western-style, to collect trash from neighborhoods, the one
service that protected Maya from obsolescence in an age of sophisticated
home-cleaning gadgetry.
Maya and her fellow dalits held
demonstrations outside the municipal commissioner’s office to stop the vans.
They finally arrived at a compromise that lets Maya and her pals collect trash
from individual homes and hand it to the vans for disposal. But Maya realizes
that this arrangement won’t last. “I got branded as polluted and became unfit
for other jobs, for what?” she wept. “To build a business that has now turned
to dust?”
Her son, however, is pleased. He
believes that this will finally force his siblings to develop skills for more
respectable work instead of joining their mother. But Maya shakes her head.
And she might be right.
Post-liberalization, the most dogged and determined dalits are able to escape
their caste-assigned destiny and get rich. But for the vast majority, as Maya
says, opportunities are better within the caste system than outside it.
Where does that leave us? If I had to make a grand claim –
which I probably shouldn’t – I would suggest that relationships of domination are
disrupted not so much because people come to reject the claims of the powerful, but because opportunities for
exit or collective action become concretely available that make these beliefs
dispensable. (Another example: the
end of footbinding and infibulation. Link is to a superb paper by Gerry Mackie - ungated here).
[update 3/3/2012: fixed some really unclear sentences]
[update 3/3/2012: fixed some really unclear sentences]
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)